CONSULTATION PAPER
IRELAND
The
Law Reform Commission
35-39
Shelbourne Road, Ballsbridge, Dublin 4
© Copyright
The Law Reform Commission 2006
First Published April 2006
THE LAW REFORM COMMISSION
Background
The Law Reform Commission is an independent statutory body
whose main aim is to keep the law under review and to make practical proposals
for its reform. It was established on 20 October 1975, pursuant to
section 3 of the Law Reform Commission Act 1975.
The Commission’s Second Programme for Law Reform, prepared
in consultation with the Attorney General, was approved by the Government and
copies were laid before both Houses of the Oireachtas in December 2000.
The Commission also works on matters which are referred to it on occasion by
the Attorney General under the terms of the Act.
To date the Commission has published 78 Reports containing
proposals for reform of the law; 11 Working Papers; 38
Consultation Papers; a number of specialised Papers for limited circulation; An
Examination of the Law of Bail; and 26 Annual Reports in accordance with
section 6 of the 1975 Act. A full list of its publications is contained
on the Commission’s website at www.lawreform.ie.
Membership
The Law Reform Commission consists of a President, one
full-time Commissioner and three part-time Commissioners.
The Commissioners at present are:
President: |
The Hon Mrs Justice Catherine McGuinness, Supreme Court |
|
|
Full-time Commissioner: |
Patricia T. Rickard-Clarke, Solicitor |
|
|
Part-time Commissioner: |
Professor Finbarr McAuley |
|
|
Marian Shanley, Solicitor |
|
|
|
Part-time Commissioner: |
Donal O’Donnell, Senior Counsel |
|
|
Secretary/Head of Administration |
John Quirke |
Research Staff
Director of Research: |
Raymond Byrne BCL, LLM (NUI), Barrister-at-Law |
|
|
Legal Researchers: |
Claire Bruton LLB, LLM (Lond), Barrister-at-Law |
|
Roberta Guiry BCL, LLM (NUI) |
|
Orla Joyce BCL, LLM (Cantab) |
|
Claire McAvinchey BCL, LLM (Glasgow) |
|
Aoife McCarthy BCL, LLM (NUI), Barrister-at-Law |
|
Richard McNamara BCL, LLM (NUI) |
|
Jane Mulcahy BCL (Law and German), LLM (NUI) |
|
Catherine Ellen O’Keeffe LLB, LLM (NUI) |
|
Sinéad Ring BCL (Law and German), LLM (NUI) |
|
Aisling Wall BCL, LLM (Cantab) |
Administration Staff
Pearse Rayel |
|
|
|
Executive Officer: |
Denis McKenna |
|
|
Legal Information Manager: |
Conor Kennedy BA, H Dip LIS |
|
|
Cataloguer: |
Eithne Boland BA (Hons), HDip Ed, HDip LIS |
|
|
Information Technology |
|
Officer: |
Liam Dargan |
|
|
Clerical Officer: |
Debbie Murray |
|
|
Principal Legal Researchers on this Consultation
Paper
Claire Hamilton
LLB (Ling Franc), Barrister-at-Law, M Litt, Dip EurCon in Human Rights
Contact Details
Further information can be obtained from:
The
Secretary/Head of Administration
The Law Reform
Commission
35-39 Shelbourne
Road, Ballsbridge, Dublin 4.
T: |
+353 1 637 7600 |
F: |
+353 1 637 7601 |
|
|
E: |
info@lawreform.ie |
W: |
www.lawreform.ie |
TABLE OF
LEGISLATION
xi
TABLE OF
CASES
xiii
CHAPTER 1 overview of The defences of
duress and necessity
CHAPTER 2 duress: General Scope and
LImitations
D Nature of
the Threats: Death or Serious Injury
F The Effect
of the Threat and Perception by the Defendant
G The
Imminence Rule and Official Protection 33
(3) Marital Coercion and
Battered Woman Syndrome
I Consideration
of Duress as a Full Defence to Murder 77
J Consideration
of Duress as a Partial Defence to Murder
(3) The Application of R v
Dudley and Stephens
(5) Reform Proposals in
England
E Necessity
as a Justificatory or Excusatory Defence
F Conclusion
on the General Scope of Necessity
CHAPTER 5 summary of Provisional
RecommendationS
1982, c. 36 |
Eng |
|
Crimes Act 1900 (New South Wales) |
|
Aus |
Crimes Act 1958 (Victoria) |
|
Aus |
Crimes Act 1961 |
1961, No. 43 |
NZ |
Crimes Amendment Act (No 2) 1999 (Australian Capital Territory) |
|
Aus |
Criminal Code Act 1899 (Queensland) |
|
Aus |
Criminal Code Act 1924 (Tasmania) |
|
Aus |
Criminal Code Act 1983 (Northern Territory) |
|
Aus |
Criminal Code Act 1995 (Australian Capital Territory) |
|
Aus |
Criminal Code Act Compilation Act 1913 (Western Australia) |
|
Aus |
Criminal Damage Act 1991 |
1991, No. 31 |
Irl |
Criminal Justice Act (Northern Ireland) 1966 |
1966, c. 20 |
NI |
Criminal Justice Act 1925 |
1925, c. 86 |
Eng |
Criminal Law Consolidation Act 1935 (South Australia) |
|
Aus |
Human Rights Act 1998 |
1998, c. 42 |
Eng |
Non Fatal Offences Against the Person Act 1997 |
1997, No. 26 |
Irl |
TABLE OF CASES
Eng |
||
Attorney General v Whelan |
Irl |
|
Attorney General v X |
[1992] ILRM 401 |
Irl |
B (a minor) v DPP |
Eng |
|
Commonwealth v Refitt |
(1912) 149 Ky 300 |
USA |
DPP for Northern Ireland v Lynch |
NI |
|
DPP v Bell |
[1992] Crim LR 176 |
Eng |
DPP v Camplin |
Eng |
|
DPP v Rogers |
Eng |
|
F, Re |
Eng |
|
HL v The United Kingdom |
45508/99 ECtHR 5 October 2004 |
CoE |
People (AG) v Keatley |
[1954] IR 12 |
Irl |
People (DPP) v Dickey |
Court of Criminal Appeal 7 March 2003 |
Irl |
People (DPP) v Kavanagh |
Court of Criminal Appeal 18 May 1999 |
Irl |
People (DPP) v Murray |
[1977] IR 360 |
Irl |
Perryman v State |
63 Ga App 819, 12 SE 2d 388 (1940) |
USA |
R v Abbott |
Eng |
|
R v Abdul-Hussain |
[1999] Crim LR 570 |
Eng |
R v Abusafiah |
(1991) 24 NSWLR 531 |
Aus |
R v Axtell |
(1660) 5 How St Tr 1146 |
Eng |
R v Bergstrom |
(1980) 52 CCC (2d) 407 |
Can |
R v Bournewood Community and Mental Health NHS Trust |
Eng |
|
R v Bowen |
Eng |
|
R v Brown and Morely |
(1968) SASR 467 |
Aus |
R v Cairns |
Eng |
|
R v Calderwood and Moore |
[1983] NI 361 |
Eng |
R v Canestra |
(1951) 2 SA 317 |
SA |
R v Carker ( No. 2) |
[1967] SCR 114 |
Can |
R v Chansie |
(1926) OPD 74 |
SA |
R v Connelly |
(1829) 2 Lew 229, 168 ER 1137 |
Eng |
R v Conway |
Eng |
|
R v Crutchley |
(1831) 5 C&P 133 |
Eng |
R v Davidson |
[1969] VR 667 |
Aus |
R v Derrington and McGauley |
[1980] VR 353 |
Aus |
R v Ditta, Hussain and Kara |
[1988] Crim LR 42 |
Eng |
R v Dudley and Stephens |
(1884) 14 QBD 273 |
Eng |
R v Fitzpatrick |
[1977] NI 20 |
Eng |
R v Foster |
(1990) 14 Crim LJ 289 |
Aus |
R v Graham |
Eng |
|
R v Harding |
[1976] VR 129 |
Aus |
R v Hasan |
Eng |
|
R v Hegarty |
[1994] Crim LR 353 |
Eng |
R v Horne |
[1994] Crim LR 584 |
Eng |
R v Howe |
[1987] All ER 771 |
Eng |
R v Hudson and Taylor |
Eng |
|
R v Hurley and Murray |
[1967] VR 526 |
Aus |
R v Joyce |
[1968] NZLR 1070 |
NZ |
R v K |
Eng |
|
R v Kray (Ronald) |
(1969) 53 Cr App Rep 569 |
Eng |
R v Latimer |
(2001) 150 CCC (3d) 129 |
Can |
R v Lawrence |
[1980] 1 NSWLR 122 |
Aus |
R v Loughnan |
[1981] VR 433 |
Aus |
R v Martin |
Eng |
|
R v Maurirere |
[2001] NZLR 431 |
NZ |
R v McCafferty |
[1974] 1 NSWLR 89 |
Aus |
R v McConnell |
[1977] 1 NSWLR 714 |
Aus |
R v McGrowther |
(1746) 18 St Tr 391 |
Eng |
R v McQuade |
NI |
|
R v Mena |
(1987) 34 CCC (3d) 304 |
Can |
R v Metwa |
(1921) TPD 227 |
SA |
R v Morgan |
[1975] 1 All ER 8 |
Eng |
R v Morgenthaler |
(1975) 53 DLR (3d) 161 |
Can |
R v Oakes |
[1995] 2 NZLR 673 |
NZ |
R v O'Brien |
[2003] NSWCCA 121 |
Aus |
R v Paquette |
(1976) 30 CCC (2d) 417 |
Can |
R v Perka |
[1984] 2 SCR 232 |
Can |
R v Pommell |
Eng |
|
R v Purdy |
(1946) 10 JCL 182 |
Eng |
R v Quayle |
Eng |
|
R v Raroa |
[1987] 2 NZLR 486 |
NZ |
R v Richmond |
[1982] Crim LR 507 |
Eng |
R v Ruzic |
[2001] 1 SCR 687 |
Can |
R v Sharp |
[1987] 3 All ER 103 |
Eng |
R v Shayler |
Eng |
|
R v Shayler |
Eng |
|
R v Shepherd |
(1988) 86 Cr App Rep 47 |
Eng |
R v Shortland |
(1996) Cr App R 116 |
Eng |
R v Smith |
(1977) 40 CRNS 390 |
Can |
R v Smyth |
[1963] VR 737 |
Aus |
R v Steane |
[1947] KB 997 |
Eng |
R v Stratton |
(1779) 21 How St Tr |
Eng |
R v Teichelman |
[1981] 2 NZLR 64 |
NZ |
R v TLC |
[2004] ABPC 79 |
Can |
R v Vermaak |
(1900) 21 NLR 204 |
SA |
R v Werner |
(1947) 2 SA 828 |
SA |
R v Wilcox |
(1976) 38 CRNS 40 |
Can |
R v Willer |
(1986) 83 Cr App Rep 225 |
Eng |
R v Williamson |
[1972] 2 NSWLR 281 |
Aus |
R v Witika |
[1993] 2 NZLR 424 |
NZ |
Reniger v Fogossa |
1552 1 Plowd 1 |
Eng |
S v Bailey |
(1982) 3 SA 772 |
SA |
S v Bradbury |
(1967) 1 SA 387 |
SA |
S v Goliath |
(1972) 3 SA 1 |
SA |
Salaca v The Queen |
[1967] NZLR 421 |
NZ |
Sheldrake v DPP, AG’s Ref (No 4 of 2004) |
Eng |
|
State (DPP) v Walsh |
[1981] IR 412 |
Irl |
US v Holmes |
26 Fed Cas 360 (1842) |
USA |
1.
This Consultation Paper on Duress and Necessity is part of a
series on defences to criminal charges.[1]
The first of these, the Consultation Paper on Homicide: The Plea of
Provocation, was published in 2003 and a third, a Consultation Paper on
Legitimate Defence is forthcoming. As noted in the Consultation Paper on
Provocation, this series is intended to provide a comprehensive review of
defences in this jurisdiction with the eventual aim of codification.[2]
2.
The pleas of duress and necessity usually provide a defence to an
individual who is constrained or coerced into committing a crime by reason of
serious threats (duress) or dire circumstances (necessity). In many cases
the defences are discussed in relation to homicide, but it is important to note
that these defences have a more general application, ranging from receiving
stolen property to unlawful possession of firearms.
3.
While the Commission discusses duress and necessity as separate defences
it is clear that there is considerable overlap between them. The defence of duress per minas (referred to in
this Consultation Paper as duress) applies when a person’s choice is
constrained by threats to do an act which would otherwise be a crime. Necessity concerns a situation where a person’s choice
is constrained due to the circumstances. As with duress, the
person acts because they are compelled to do so, not by threats from a person,
but by threats arising from the circumstances in which they find
themselves.
4.
Chapter 1 outlines briefly the defences of duress and necessity and
introduces the concept of constrained choice to provide a general framework for
discussion of the defences.
5.
Chapter 2 deals with the general scope of and limitations to the defence
of duress. It considers whether duress should be regarded as an
excusatory or a justificatory defence. It discusses whether the threat
should be of ‘death or serious bodily harm’ and whether the test for this
should be objective or subjective. It also deals with the target and the
effect of the threat. The chapter also includes a discussion of the
reasonableness requirement in relation to both the belief in the threat and the
response to the threat. It goes on to discuss the requirement of
imminence of the threat and how this relates to the requirement that the
accused seek official protection. The chapter then examines whether a
person ought reasonably to have foreseen the likelihood of being subjected to
threats and, if so, whether this should be a reason to disallow the defence.
It goes on to discuss the defence of marital coercion which existed at
common law and its existence in other jurisdictions. Finally, the burden
of proof that applies where duress is raised as a defence is discussed.
6.
Chapter 3 discusses the application of the defence of duress to murder.
Under current Irish law, it appears that duress is a general defence to all
crimes except murder, attempted murder and treason.
7.
Chapter 4 reviews the scope of the defence of necessity and its
relationship with duress. It also deals with the relatively new defence
of duress of circumstances in English law, including a comparison between this
defence and both duress and necessity.
8.
Chapter 5 contains a summary of the Commission’s provisional
recommendations.
9.
This Consultation Paper is intended to form the basis for discussion and
accordingly the recommendations made are provisional in nature. Following
further consideration of the issues and consultation with interested parties,
the Commission will make its final recommendations. Submissions on the
provisional recommendations contained in this Consultation Paper are
welcome. In order that the Commission’s final Report may be made
available as soon as possible, those who wish to do so are requested to send
their submissions in writing by post to the Commission or by email to
info@lawreform.ie by 30 September 2006.
1.01
In modern legal systems the defences of duress and necessity cater for
cases where the defendant breaks the law in circumstances where his freedom of
choice was constrained by serious threats. Typically the defendant breaks
the law rather than see the threats carried out. The plea of duress
applies in cases where the threats emanate from a human source and have the
form ‘Do this or else’; whereas the plea of necessity covers situations where
the threats are circumstantial or non-human in origin.
1.02
Most common law systems stress the element of constrained choice as the
conceptual or theoretical basis for the defences of duress and necessity.
Emphasis on the element of constrained choice highlights the gravamen or inner
nature of the defendant’s predicament, while at the same time underlining the
essential difference between the pleas of necessity and duress and those of
physical coercion or force majeure.[3]
In a situation of physical coercion the defendant has no choice;[4] as would be true, for example, where he
causes the death of a pedestrian as a result of his car being blown off course
by a sudden storm. In contrast, in situations of duress and necessity the
defendant faces a moral dilemma. Through no fault of his own, he is
placed in the difficult predicament of having to choose between abiding by the
law and becoming a victim of violence, or breaking the law in order to protect
himself or another from the threat of serious assault or mortal danger.
1.03
In cases of duress per minas[5]
the defendant admits both the material and mental elements of the offence
charged but claims that he acted under the compulsion of threats made by
another person.[6]
In most legal systems, the threats must be of death or serious injury to the
accused or another person; and must be sufficiently serious to overwhelm the
powers of resistance of an ordinary person.[7]
1.04
Perhaps the best-known example of duress in Irish law arose in Attorney
General v Whelan.[8] There the defendant admitted that
he had knowingly received stolen property, but claimed that he acted under
pressure of serious threats. The Court of Criminal Appeal held that he
was entitled to the defence of duress in these circumstances and set out the
essential conditions of the plea in Irish law.
1.05
If successful, the plea of duress affords a complete defence.
1.06
Strictly speaking, duress is a species of the larger genus of
necessity. Indeed, it might be said that the two pleas are identical in
every respect bar one: in necessity the threat to the defendant comes from
natural or circumstantial rather than human sources. Typically the
defendant breaks the law in order to spare himself or another from an impending
calamity. For example, he forces his way into private property in order
to rescue elderly residents from a blaze.[9]
1.07
The defence of necessity has never been recognised as such in English
law, but the Commission notes that the English courts have fashioned a plea of
duress of circumstances which functions as a defence of necessity in all but
name.[10]
The new plea was developed by analogy with the traditional defence of duress
and, accordingly, attracts all of the limiting conditions attached to the
original. Thus the circumstantial threat must be one of death or serious
injury, and such that a person endowed with ordinary human fortitude would have been unable to resist.
1.08
It is useful to distinguish cases where the defendant chooses the lesser
of two evils from those in which he is faced with a choice of comparable
evils. In some civilian systems, the former are treated as instances of
justified (as opposed to excused) conduct, and, accordingly, give rise to a
complete defence on the grounds that the defendant has done the right thing in
the circumstances. In practice this distinction is unimportant since in
most legal systems a defendant who makes the wrong choice in difficult circumstances
will still be excused on the grounds of duress or necessity.
1.09
However, the distinction is relevant to the discussion of whether the
pleas of duress and duress of circumstances should be extended to murder.
If it is agreed that a killer who effects a net saving of human life in a
situation of severe moral compulsion has done the right thing in the
circumstances, then it follows that duress and necessity should be a complete
answer to murder; and, on the principle of fair labelling, that the accused is
entitled to be acquitted on the grounds of lesser evils rather than duress or
necessity simpliciter.
1.10
On the other hand, if the focus is on the element of constrained choice
rather than choice of evils, the Commission acknowledges that the case for
allowing duress and necessity to operate as partial defences to murder can be
coherently made.
1.11
The ensuing discussion will be guided by the basic principles set out in
this Chapter.
2.01
The defence of duress applies when a person is compelled by threats to
do an act, which would otherwise be a crime, where the person believes that the
threats will be carried out. In this Chapter, the Commission discusses
the general scope and limitations to the defence of duress.
2.02
The Chapter begins with a discussion of the only Irish case in the
modern era to discuss duress, Attorney General v Whelan[11].
The remainder of the Chapter discusses the scope and limitations of the defence
under the following headings; whether it should be regarded as excusatory or
justificatory in nature; nature of the threats; target of the threats; the
effect of the threats; the imminence rule and exposure to the risk of duress.
This chapter also discusses the defence of marital coercion which existed
at common law, and the burden of proof in relation to duress. In Chapter
3, the Commission considers the application of the
defence to homicide.
2.03
The only Irish case which has examined the nature and scope of the
defence of duress is the 1933 decision of the Court of Criminal Appeal in Attorney
General v Whelan.[12]
2.04
The defendant was charged with having received a sum of stolen money,
knowing it to be stolen. He had also been indicted, with others, on a
charge of conspiracy to steal a quantity of money from a train but was found
not guilty on the conspiracy charge. Another man, Farnan, had also been
indicted on the conspiracy charge and had pleaded guilty. Farnan had
brought a box of coins which had been stolen in the train robbery to the
defendant’s house late one night. The defendant admitted he had accepted the
money but said that he had done so under duress from Farnan, who was armed with
a revolver.
2.05
The trial judge noted that there was no doubt that Farnan was the type
of man to threaten to use a revolver, if not actually use it, and he left it to
the jury to decide whether the defendant had acted under duress. He posed a
special question to the jury, which was “[I]n receiving the money did Peter
Whelan act under threats of immediate death or serious personal violence?”[13] The jury answered in the
affirmative.
2.06
The trial judge then ruled that although the defendant had acted under
duress, this was not a defence but rather would act as mitigation in
sentencing. On appeal to the Court of Criminal Appeal, the defendant
contended that the finding of the jury that he had acted under duress amounted
to an acquittal.
2.07
It was noted by the Court of Criminal Appeal that authorities on whether
acting under duress should entitle a defendant to an acquittal were rare, and
indeed showed a degree of discrepancy.[14]
The Court noted that, as a result of this, the case had to be decided on the
basis of general principle.
2.08
The Court went on to outline the scope of the defence. In relation to
threats, it was held that “[t]hreats of immediate death or serious personal
violence so great as to overbear the ordinary power of human resistance should
be accepted as a justification for acts which would otherwise be criminal.”[15]
2.09
The Court noted, however, that the application of the general rule must
be subject to certain limitations. The Court stated that “where the
excuse of duress is applicable it must further be clearly shown that the
overpowering of the will was operative at the time the crime was actually
committed, and, if there were reasonable opportunity for the will to reassert
itself, no justification can be found in antecedent threats”.[16]
2.10
Thus, the general scope of the defence of duress, as outlined in Whelan,
is that; the will of the defendant must have been overborne by the threats, the
duress must be operating when the offence is committed and if there is an
opportunity for the individual will to reassert itself and it is not taken, a
plea of duress will fail.
2.11
In the particular circumstances, the Court of Criminal Appeal held that
the appellant’s conviction should not stand and directed a verdict of acquittal
to be entered.
2.12
The Court also stated, obiter, that the plea of duress does not
extend to the offence of murder and this will be discussed further below in relation
to the scope of the defence.[17]
2.13
As far as the Commission can ascertain, although Attorney-General v
Whelan has been cited in various cases in other jurisdictions[18] there has been little judicial
consideration in Ireland of the nature and scope of the defence of duress since
1933.[19]
In
People (DPP) v Dickey,[20] the Court of Criminal Appeal applied, without an
extensive analysis, the approach taken in Whelan.[21]
2.14
In other jurisdictions there has been considerable discussion of the
nature and scope of the defence. The Commission therefore considers that
it is appropriate to discuss those more recent developments in the context of
this Consultation Paper.
2.15
The most recent statement of the general scope of and limitations to the
defence of duress in English law was given by the House of Lords in R v
Hasan.[22] In
this case, the primary issue was the denial of the defence on the basis that
the defendant has voluntarily exposed himself or herself to the risk of
threats.[23]
The House of Lords, however, also reviewed the general scope of the
defence. It was noted that certain distinguishing features of the defence
include that it is a complete, rather than a reductive, defence; that it is
excusatory; that the victim is usually morally innocent and that the burden of
proof lies with the prosecution to prove that the defendant did not act under
duress. Lord Bingham noted that, given these features, it is unsurprising that
the defence of duress should so far have developed within narrowly defined
limits, and he went on to state that these features would encourage him “where
policy choices are to be made, towards tightening rather than relaxing the
conditions to be met before duress may be successfully relied on.”[24]
2.16
The limitations laid out by the House of Lords in R v Hasan are
as follows:
·
The threat or danger must be of death or serious injury;
· The
threat must be directed against the defendant, his or her immediate family or
someone close to the defendant;
· The
relevant tests are in general objective, with reference to the reasonableness
of the defendant’s perceptions and conduct;
· The
defence is available only where the criminal conduct which it is sought to
excuse has been directly caused by the threats relied upon;
· There
must have been no evasive action the defendant could reasonably have been
expected to take;
· The
defendant must not voluntarily have laid himself or herself open to the duress
relied upon;
· Duress
may be a defence to any crime except some forms of treason, murder and
attempted murder.
2.17
In R v Hasan, the defendant had been convicted of aggravated
burglary. At trial, his defence was that he had been coerced into
committing the burglary after threats were made to harm him and his
family. The person who had threatened him was, according to the defendant,
a drug dealer with a reputation for violence but the defendant had an
association with him. The defendant’s appeal against conviction was
allowed by the Court of Appeal and his conviction was quashed. However
the prosecution appealed successfully to the House of Lords, who restored the
defendant’s conviction and outlined the above limitations.
2.18
The Commission notes here that, in recent English law a defence of
duress of circumstances has been developed by analogy with duress, and that
these limitations apply to both defences. The defence of duress of
circumstances will be discussed further below.[25]
2.19
The defence of duress was considered in the Australian case R v
Hurley and Murray[26] in which Smith J outlined a working
definition of the defence. It has been noted that this has been widely
accepted as a correct statement of the position of the defence at common law.[27] The accused is required to have
committed the crime he or she has been charged with in all of the following
circumstances:
· When
the accused was under a threat that death or grievous bodily harm would be
inflicted upon a human being if he or she failed to do the act;
· Where
the circumstances were such that a person of ordinary firmness would have been
likely to yield to the threat in the way the accused did;
· Where
the threat was present and continuing, imminent and impending;
· Where
the accused reasonably apprehended that the threat would be carried out;
· Where
the threat induced the defendant to commit the crime;
· Where
the crime was not murder, nor any other crime so heinous as to be excluded from
the doctrine;
· Where
the accused did not expose himself or herself to the threat by their own
volition;
· Where
the accused had no means to safely prevent the execution of the threat.
2.20
The defence of duress operates to exonerate a person for what would
otherwise be a crime as “an expression of compassion for one of our kind caught
in a maelstrom of circumstances.”[28]
2.21
There has been some debate as to whether the defence of duress operates
as an excusatory defence or justificatory defence. If the defence is
excusatory, it is clear that the action of the person was a crime, but the
criminal justice system recognises that the person had very limited choice in
the matter and thus it would be unfair to place criminal responsibility on
them. If a defence is justificatory, it is recognised that the action of
the person was not a crime as it was the correct action to have taken in that
particular set of circumstances.
2.22
Generally the defence of duress is seen as an excusatory defence because
the person argues that his or her will was overborne by threats, and that
although the act was a crime, no criminal sanction should follow due to the
constrained choice that the person was faced with.[29]
2.23
It has been pointed out that the case law on duress firmly supports its
status as an excusatory defence.[30] While Murnaghan J in Attorney
General v Whelan[31] used the words ‘justification’ and ‘excuse’ almost
interchangeably, the Commission agrees with the view of Lord Morris in DPP
for Northern Ireland v Lynch[32] that the word ‘excuse’ is the more appropriate term in
this context. Subject to the views of the Commission on the application
of duress to murder,[33]
the Commission is of the opinion that this is appropriate and thus, the
Commission provisionally recommends that the status of duress as an excusatory
defence in general terms be retained.
2.24
The Commission provisionally recommends that the status of the
defence of duress as an excusatory defence in general terms should be retained.
2.25
In Attorney General v Whelan,[34] the defendant was under threats which
were accepted to amount to threats of “death or serious violence”. In that
case, no actual threats were made to the defendant, but it was noted that the
presence of the threatener, who was armed and was the kind of person who would
not hesitate to use the revolver, was sufficient to amount to a threat of
“death or serious violence”.
2.26
The Court of Criminal Appeal held that “[t]hreats of immediate death or
serious personal violence so great as to overbear the ordinary power of human
resistance should be accepted as a justification for acts which would otherwise
be criminal.”
2.27
The definition of duress propounded by Professor Glanville Williams[35]
refers simply to threats of physical harm, but the weight of authority suggests
that the threats must be of death or serious injury.[36] It was suggested in R v Steane[37] that
a threat of false imprisonment would suffice for duress and this was echoed by
Lord Simon (in the minority) in DPP for Northern Ireland v Lynch[38]
when he observed that the law on this point is not definite and that a
threatened loss of liberty may suffice. However, he dismissed the idea
that a threat to property would be sufficient.
2.28
The Law Commission recommended in its 1977 Report on Defences of
General Application that the threats should be of death or serious personal
injury which should be defined to include mental as well as physical injury.[39] The Commission’s 1985 Report, Codification
of the Criminal Law, stated that a threat must have been made to kill or
cause serious injury.[40]
The threat of mental injury was removed because, as the Commission noted,
“injury” would be a wide enough term to include “injury to the state of a man’s
mind”.[41]
2.29
In 1989, the Law Commission in its Report on a Criminal Code for
England and Wales, the Commission recommended that one of the conditions of
the defence was that the threat must be “one of death or serious personal harm
to himself or another.”[42]
The Commission noted that this followed the prevailing judicial view and that
of most modern codes. In 1993, in its Report on Offences against the Person
and General Principles the Commission again recommended that the threat
must be of death or serious injury.[43]
2.30
Section 17 of the Canadian Criminal Code[44] requires the threat to be “of immediate
death or bodily harm”. Until the adoption of this Criminal Code in 1982
the threats had to be of death or grievous bodily harm.
2.31
The Canadian Law Reform Commission (“CLRC”) recommended in its 1982
Working Paper on Criminal
Law: the General Part that the level of threats be “threats of serious
and immediate bodily harm.”[45]
2.32
In its later Report, Recodifying Criminal Law[46],
the CLRC made the following recommendation in relation to duress in which there
is no requirement that the threats are physical in nature: “No one is liable
for committing a crime in reasonable response to threats of immediate serious
harm to himself or another person unless he himself purposely causes the death
of, or seriously harms, another person.”[47]
2.33
In R v Hurley
and Murray, [48] it was noted that a threat of
“death or grievous bodily harm” was necessary in order for the accused to plead
duress. The defence of duress is clearly open to an accused faced with
threats of death or serious bodily injury. The threat of imprisonment has
received some support,[49]
although it has been suggested that this could be
regarded as an implied threat to kill or cause serious bodily injury if the
demands of the kidnappers are not met.[50]
It has been noted that it appears unlikely that threats to property will be
recognised as sufficient to afford the defendant a plea of duress.[51]
2.34
The Western Australian Code and the Queensland Code both refer to
threats of “immediate death or grievous bodily harm.”[52] The provisions of the Australian
Capital Territory and Commonwealth Codes refer merely to threats, and do not
elaborate on the nature of the threats.
2.35
The 1980 Report of the Law Reform Commission of Victoria on Duress, Necessity and
Coercion recommended that in cases of murder, where the accused intended
or expected death to occur as a result of his or her actions, the harm threatened
should be one of “death or serious personal injury (mental or physical).”[53]
In other cases of murder and indictable injuries to the person, the harm
threatened should be the same, or be “torture, rape, buggery or
imprisonment.” In all other cases, threats could apply to property,
livelihood and reputation, if the person threatened cannot fairly be expected
to suffer the risk.
2.36
The Law Reform Commission of Victoria again considered the nature of the
threats in 2004 and agreed with the Model Criminal Code Officers Report that a
limitation of the defence to situations where threats were of death or serious
bodily harm was not required.[54]
The Commission was of the opinion that, consistent with the law on
self-defence, it is unlikely that a jury would acquit a person of murder, on
the basis of a defence of duress, except where that person was threatened with
very serious harm.[55]
2.37
In New Zealand, under the Crimes Act 1961,
the harm threatened must be of death or grievous bodily harm. Like
Canada, however, there is no additional requirement that the threatened harm be
sufficiently serious to induce a person of ordinary firmness to act as the
accused did. Threats of mere harm, however, will not suffice. In R
v Maurirere[56] it
was held that grievous bodily harm meant “harm which will seriously interfere
for a time with health and comfort” and was “really serious”. In that
case the defendant had been the victim of a serious assault from her boyfriend
in the past and there was corroborative evidence that she had been seen with black
eyes. This was found to be insufficient for the purposes of the Crimes
Act.
2.38
As will be discussed further below, South African law has a defence of
necessity which covers situations where an accused’s choice is constrained
either by human agents (duress or compulsion) or by virtue of the surrounding
circumstances (necessity).[57]
2.39
One of the requirements for an act to be justified on the ground of
necessity is that a legal interest of the accused must be endangered. The
case law establishes that, while threats of death or serious bodily injury will
certainly trigger the defence, threats of lesser injury to the person and of
damage to property will also suffice.[58] However, this
does not extend to threats of mere pecuniary loss[59] and
the existence and nature of the threats are judged objectively.[60] It
has been argued that the defence should apply regardless of the nature of the
legal interest threatened, provided the other requirements are met,[61] and it is easy to see the merit in this
argument given the existence of the final requirement which requires the
competing interests to be weighed against each other. In order for the
defence to be successful the evil avoided must be greater than the evil caused
by the infringement of the law.
2.40
While a threat of death or serious injury is usually required to trigger
the operation of the defence, in many State jurisdictions in the United States
there has been a tendency to look to the gravity of the offence charged.
If the offence is not of a very serious nature, the court may hold that a
threat of less than death or serious bodily injury will suffice. Thus, in
the trial of a regulatory offence, it was held by the Supreme Court of
Kentucky, that the jury should be instructed that the defendant had a defence
if compelled to commit the act under “such violence or threats as… inspire a
just fear of great injury to person, reputation or property.”[62] The
defence cannot generally be invoked in respect of threats of future harm;
however, in Georgia, it was held that, in certain circumstances, a threat of
future harm may suffice to excuse a prohibited act.[63]
2.41
The requirement of “death or serious injury” forms the first objective
criterion in the current test for duress. It is arguable that a threshold
criterion is unnecessary given the general objective requirement that the
accused display reasonable fortitude. If duress acts as a concession to
human weakness, it can be argued that the law should recognise that every type
of threatened harm is capable of triggering the defence, provided that it would
overwhelm a person of normal reasonable steadfastness in the accused’s
situation. Another option for reform is that the degree of threat should
not be fixed in this way and that a proportionality test should be introduced,
allowing comparison between the threat and the crime charged.
2.42
To change the test to a “balancing of harms” test, based on
proportionality, moves the focus of the defence away from its traditional
excusatory base (focus on the actor) to a justificatory one (focus on the act).
It is certainly arguable that a proportionality test between the threat and the
crime charged could be fairer. Some examples given by Lord Simon in DPP
for Northern Ireland v Lynch
serve to illustrate the point: the threat to burn down a defendant’s house of
England and Wales unless he or she keeps watch while a crime is committed or a
fugitive from justice who may say “I have it in my power to make your son
bankrupt. You may avoid that by driving me to the airport.”[64]
2.43
A proportionality test would allow threats to be regarded by the court
or jury cumulatively, for example, threats to reveal a defendant’s disreputable
past as well as to cause him or her serious injury.
2.44
However the Commission recognises the argument that it may prove
extremely difficult to balance the harms in question, for example, balancing a
threat of severe injury to the person against a compelled disclosure of
information which might endanger national security.[65] Additionally, although the
proportionality test may appear fairer in theory, there is a possibility that
in practice a proportionality test could be too vague and may be difficult to
elaborate with precision.
2.45
If the accused is acting under the influence of threats which would
cause a person of ordinary firmness to act in the manner in which he or she
did, it is possible that he or she will commit the crime, regardless of its
severity. As Howard notes, “this may be a small crime or a great one but
it has no necessary connection with the threats.”[66]
2.46
However the other aspects of the defence, for example, the reasonable
fortitude test, arguably render superfluous an additional test of
proportionality.
2.47
In the Commission’s view, given that the accused acting under duress has
injured an innocent victim, society is entitled to expect that an individual
should resist threats which fall below a minimum level of severity. The
law must draw a line somewhere and it chooses to do so between threats to
bodily integrity and threats to property. However it is possible that a
threat of death or serious bodily harm is not necessarily the worst of dangers.
Thus, for example, torture may cause extreme pain without any residual bodily
injury.
2.48
The older authorities are not clear on this aspect of the defence.[67] Almost all common law
jurisdictions have confined the defence of duress by the use of a limitation on
the basis of the threat. The rule also finds support in modern authority
and as already noted, various law reform bodies which have examined the defence
have likewise recommended that only threats of death or serious harm should
supply the defence. The Commission has concluded that this is the correct
approach to this issue.
2.49
The Commission provisionally recommends that the threat which
underpins the defence of duress should be one of death or serious harm.
2.50
The issue here is to whom the threats should be directed. In most
duress cases, the threats will have been directed at the accused, but it is
possible that they may be directed at a third party. Attorney General
v Whelan[68]
did not refer to this issue.
2.51
In People (AG) v Keatley[69] however, there is a reference to the issue, and although
that is not a duress case, it is of relevance. In that case, it was held,
in relation to self-defence, that the right of the use of force in self-defence
also applies to the defence of others, and that no special relationship is
necessary between the parties. Potentially, a similar approach may be
relevant to the law of duress in Ireland.
2.52
It appears that, in English law, it is possible to avail of the defence
of duress if the threats are to third parties.[70] There is a requirement, however,
that the threat must be directed against the defendant, his immediate family or
someone close to the defendant. This was affirmed in the recent House of
Lords decision R v
Hasan[71]
in which Lord Bingham referred to the Judicial Studies Board’s specimen
direction which stated that the threat must be directed, if not to the
defendant or a member of his immediate family, to a person for whose safety the
defendant would reasonably regard himself as responsible. Although this
point was not at issue in R v Hasan, Lord
Bingham noted that this direction appeared to be in line with the rationale of
the defence of duress.
2.53
The Law Commission of England and Wales noted in 1993 that there was
little authority on this point and recommended that the defence should be
founded when the threat is made to anyone, on the grounds that this aspect is
more properly taken into account when assessing the overall reasonableness of
the accused’s response to the threat.[72]
2.54
The Draft Legislation proposed by the Canadian Law Reform Commission in
1982 referred to the target of the threats, an issue on which section 17 of the
Canadian Criminal Code was silent.[73]
The proposed section limited the defence of duress to threats made against
those under the accused’s protection, for example, family members.
2.55
In its later Report of 1986, Recodifying Criminal Law,
the Canadian Law Reform Commission recommended that the defence be broadened by
allowing threats to include any person, not just someone under the protection
of the accused.[74]
2.56
At common law in Australia, it appears that the defence is not confined
to cases where the threat is made to the accused or persons to whom he or she
may be closely connected: the requirement is simply that the threats pertain to
a “human being”.[75]
None of the Codes make any reference to the potential target of the threat.
2.57
The Law Reform Commission of Victoria recommended in 1977 that the harm
threatened must be directed at the accused or someone closely connected with
him.[76]
More recently, however, the Commission recommended, in relation to the
application of duress to homicide, that the nature of the threat need not reach
a certain level, as discussed above, and in the accompanying draft provisions,
made no recommendation that the threat should be directed at certain persons.[77]
2.58
There appears to be no requirement under the current Irish case-law that
the threats must be issued against the defendant personally or even against
someone with whom the accused has a special relationship.[78] However it is necessary to
remember that the threat must also be one which the actor could not reasonably
be expected to bear. If the threats are directed against a stranger, it
will prove more difficult to satisfy this requirement. As one group of commentators
argue, “a defence of duress is unlikely to be accepted as compelling defendants
into the commission of a crime unless the threat is made either to their
immediate family or to some other person to whom they are exceptionally close.”[79] Further, the party to whom the
threat is directed can be of relevance in establishing whether the accused has
in fact been compelled to commit the crime.
2.59
In the Commission’s view there are strong arguments in favour of
allowing the subject of the threats to be anyone at all. By analogy with
the law on self defence, the defence should be available where a threat of
death or serious harm is directed towards any person. It is possible that
a threat of death or serious injury to a close friend of the defendant may be
equally as compelling as a threat to a relative. Furthermore, it is
unnecessary to require that the threats be directed at a specific person as
this element will be adequately catered for by the question whether the
defendant has responded reasonably to the threat.
2.60
However, if the defence is to be available, even to a limited extent, in
homicide cases, it may be necessary to reconsider this approach.
2.61
The Commission provisionally recommends that the defence of duress
should be available where a threat of death or serious harm is directed towards
any person and that there should be no restriction in the availability of the
defence in relation to the target of the threats.
2.62
In Attorney General v Whelan,[80] the Court of Criminal Appeal held that the will of the
defendant must be overborne by the threats. The Court noted that the
threats of immediate death or serious personal violence must be “so great as to
overbear the ordinary power of human resistance”.[81]
2.63
The Court of Criminal Appeal in People (DPP) v Dickey[82]
noted that the trial judge in that case had correctly applied the decision in Attorney
General v Whelan. The trial judge had told the jury that in
considering whether the defendant had acted under duress, “it is not what you
would do in the situation but what you perceive the accused’s powers were, and
take into account the particular circumstances and human frailties of the
accused specifically.”
2.64
The approach of the Court in Attorney General v Whelan was
subsequently cited by Lord Edmund Davies in DPP for Northern Ireland v Lynch.[83]
2.65
As to the effect of the threat on the defendant, the standard is
objective. In R v Graham[84]
the Court of Appeal held that the defendant is required to have the
“steadfastness reasonably to be expected of the ordinary citizen in his
situation” although it was noted that until then there had been little by way
of authority on the nature of the test. The decision in Graham was approved by the House of Lords in
R v Howe.[85]
2.66
In R v Graham,
Lord Lane CJ, drawing an analogy with the defence of provocation,
held that a defendant’s fortitude should be measured against that of a “sober
person of reasonable firmness”. Thus, while in provocation the
characteristic which must be viewed objectively is self control, in duress it
is firmness of purpose. However, like the reasonable man invoked in DPP
v Camplin[86]
in laying down a test for provocation, the “sober person of reasonable
firmness” is to be endowed with such permanent[87] characteristics of the defendant as sex,
age and physical health. Moreover, drawing on the analogy with provocation
where a similar test is used, it is likely that the jury may also take into
account characteristics of the defendant bearing on the gravity of the
threat to him or her.[88]
2.67
Subsequent case law of the Court of Appeal has resulted in only one
addition to the list of relevant characteristics. In R v Bowen[89] the
Court noted obiter that
a “recognised mental illness or psychiatric condition, such as post traumatic
stress disorder” could be taken into account. For the most part, however,
the Court has been reluctant to admit evidence outside the categories of age,
sex, physical and mental disability, fearing that this would dilute the objectivity
of the reasonable firmness test. In Bowen itself it was
held that evidence of low intelligence, falling short of a mental disability,
was not admissible and in R v Hegarty[90] the
Court found that medical evidence of the defendant’s personality disorder which
rendered him emotionally unstable had been properly excluded. Similarly,
in R v Horne[91] the Court ruled that evidence of
personal vulnerability or pliancy had been correctly ruled out.
2.68
In R v Hasan,[92],
the House of Lords noted that “the relevant tests pertaining to duress have
been largely stated objectively, with reference to the reasonableness of the
defendant’s perceptions and not, as is usual in many other areas of the
criminal law, with primary reference to his subjective perceptions.”
2.69
In relation to proposed reform on the issue, the Law Commission recommended
in 1977 that the threat must be such that the defendant could not reasonably be
expected to resist it in all the circumstances of the case, including the
nature of the offence, the defendant’s belief as to the threat, and any other
relevant personal circumstances. The Law Commission took the view that
“threats directed against a weak, immature or disabled person may well be much
more compelling than the same threats directed against a normal healthy
person.”[93]
2.70
The substance of this recommendation was incorporated into the Law
Commission’s draft Criminal Code Bill in 1985[94] with the modification that the phrase
“personal characteristics that affect [the] gravity [of the threat]” was
considered to be more precise than “any of his personal characteristics which
are relevant.[95]
2.71
In the Law Commission’s Report on a Criminal Code in 1989, most
of the recommendations followed the Law Commission’s earlier recommendations.[96] The main test remained the
question of whether the “threat is one which in all the circumstances
(including any of his personal circumstances that affect its gravity) he cannot
reasonably be expected to resist”.[97]
This would allow evidence of an individual’s personal vulnerability to be
considered by the jury. The Law Commission restated its view that a
reasonableness requirement should not be imposed in relation to the accused’s
perception of the surrounding circumstances. It was argued that it was
important to bring the law on duress in line with the law on self defence and
with the general policy of the Criminal Code that reasonableness should be a
matter of evidence only. It is notable, therefore, that in reducing the
significance of the objective element in the above two respects, the
Commission’s views run counter to the dicta of the Court of
Appeal in Graham.
2.72
In 1993 the Commission again examined the area of duress, in the Report
on the Criminal Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences Against the
Person and General Principles.[98]
It identified certain areas of particular concern, two of which were relevant
to the threat. The first, as noted below, was whether the actor’s belief
in the existence, nature or seriousness of the threat must be reasonably
held.
2.73
The second question addressed was whether the “reasonable steadfastness”
requirement should be retained. The recommendation of the Commission in
this regard remained unchanged from 1985, namely, that the threat/danger was
one “which in all the circumstances (including any of the defendant’s personal
characteristics that affect its gravity) he cannot reasonably be expected to
resist.” The Commission argued that to deny the defence to the
“objectively weak” would be futile and would also be inconsistent with the
purpose of the defence not to enforce unrealistically high standards of
behaviour.
2.74
In a recent Law Commission Consultation Paper[99] the Law Commission noted, in the light
of its provisional recommendation that duress be made available as a partial
defence to “first degree murder,”[100] that the relevance of characteristics
should be pared down in order to achieve consistency with the recommendations
that it makes on the partial defence of provocation. Thus, the Law
Commission recommends that the defendant’s age and “all the circumstances of
the defendant other than those which bear on his capacity to withstand duress”
would be relevant for the purpose of the objective test in R v Graham.[101]
Thus, the ‘firm proposal’ of the Law Commission as regards the effect of the
threats on the defendant is as follows; “In deciding whether a person of
reasonable firmness would have acted as the defendant did, the jury can take
into account all the circumstances of the defendant including his age other
than those which bear upon his capacity to withstand duress.”[102]
2.75
In R v Graham[103] the Court of Appeal imposed another significant
objective requirement in relation to duress, namely, that a defendant cannot
rely on an unreasonable belief of fact in order to establish the defence.
The jury should be directed to enquire as to whether “the [defendant] was
impelled to act as he did because, as a result of what he reasonably believed
[the duressor] had said or done, he had good cause to fear
that if he did not so act [the duressor] would kill him or … cause him serious
injury”.[104]
This requires defendants first, to place a reasonable interpretation on the
words or actions of the duressor and, secondly, even if they satisfy this
requirement, the impression so formed must constitute adequate grounds for
their fear of death or serious injury.
2.76
This principle has been repeatedly followed by the Court of Appeal in
England, with some exceptions.[105] Thus,
in R v Cairns[106] the
Court held that the relevant question for the jury was the reasonableness of
the defendant’s perception of the threat not the existence in actual fact of
the threat.
2.77
In R v Hasan[107],
the trial judge put the following question to the jury: “Was the defendant
driven or forced to act as he did by threats which, rightly or wrongly, he genuinely
believed that if he did not burgle [the] house, his family would be seriously
harmed or killed?”[108]
In the House of Lords, this question was not challenged by the appellant, but
Lord Bingham makes reference to the formulation of R v Graham and R v
Howe in relation to belief and notes that this formulation is followed in
the present case save in one respect. He went on to note that the trial
judge had, “very properly,” based his judgment on the Judicial Studies Board’s
specimen direction of August 2000, thus including the words “genuinely
believed” as opposed to “reasonably believed”. Lord Bingham noted that
while it is essential that the threats are genuinely, that is actually,
believed, “there is no warrant for relaxing the requirement that the belief
must be reasonable as well as genuine.”[109]
2.78
In 1993 the Law Commission of England and Wales examined the defence of
duress, as part of a report on offences against the person.[110] It identified certain areas of
particular concern, two of which were relevant to the threat. First, must
the actor’s belief in the existence, nature or seriousness of the threat be
reasonably held? The Law Commission reiterated its previous view that a
defendant should be entitled to rely on an honest, but unreasonable belief and
that reasonableness should be an evidential consideration only. In so
doing, it observed that this would bring the law on duress in line with recent
judicial developments and with the general policy of the proposed legislation
as a whole.[111]
The second question which was addressed in this Report was whether the
“reasonable steadfastness” requirement should be retained and this is discussed
above.
2.79
In the more recent Law Commission Consultation Paper, A New Homicide
Act for England and Wales?,[112]
the Law Commission addresses the need for the defendant’s view of the nature of
the threat to be objectively reasonable. It is noted that the previous
opinion of the Law Commission was that the belief had to be honest, but not
necessarily reasonable. In this Consultation Paper, the Law Commission
reconsiders this and notes that “there must be a reasonable basis for a belief
in death or life-threatening harm.”[113]
2.80
Section 17 of the Canadian Criminal Code requires a belief that the
threats will be carried out, thus mandating a subjective assessment of the
particular accused’s belief and consideration of his or her individual
strengths and weaknesses. This differs from the English definition
because the effectiveness of the threats is tested against the particular
defendant rather than the reasonable man.[114] However, Stuart notes that the
courts have not always applied the test in a manner faithful to the subjective
nature of section 17.[115]
2.81
The Canadian Law Reform Commission (CLRC) in its 1982 Working Paper
included a “reasonable response” requirement.[116]
2.82
This requirement would mean that there would be no defence available to
accused persons unless their belief in the threats was a reasonable one, thus
bringing Canadian law in line with English law. The reasonable response
requirement was retained in the later report of the CLRC in 1987.[117]
2.83
As already noted, in R v Hurley and Murray,[118]
various requirements that the accused must meet before he may avail of the
defence of duress were set out for the law in Victoria. The requirements
relevant to the threat were that:
· the
circumstances were such that a person of ordinary firmness would have been
likely to yield to the threat in the way the accused did;
· the
accused reasonably apprehended that the threat would be carried out;
· the
threat induced the defendant to commit the crime.
2.84
However, it should be noted that the normative test laid down in Hurley and Murray (that
the threat was such that it might have caused a
reasonable person placed in the same situation to take similar action) is a
less stringent test than that laid down by the English Court of Appeal in R v Graham[119]
(which requires the prosecution to prove that a person of reasonable firmness would not have
responded to the threat in the manner in which the accused did).[120]
2.85
There are considerable differences between the Australian States as to
the nature of the test for duress. Under common law and the 1983 Northern
Territory Code,[121]
the test for duress is objective so that a precondition to the defence is that
a reasonable person placed in the same situation could or would have acted as
the accused did. Under the older Codes, however, the test would appear to
be subjective. The Tasmanian provision, for example, is couched in
completely subjective terms.[122]
2.86
In 2004, in a report on Defences to Homicide, the Law Reform
Commission of Victoria discussed the objective and subjective tests, and noted
that the Law Commission of England and Wales included subjective elements with
an objective reasonableness requirement in relation to the accused’s response.[123]
The 1980 Law Reform Commission of Victoria Report had recommended this
approach, as well as the proposal that the jury asked whether the accused was
morally culpable, and if not, that he be acquitted.[124]
2.87
In the 2004 Report, the Law Reform Commission of Victoria proposed that
an objective test of reasonableness be applied. Therefore a person would
only be able to rely on duress if he or she subjectively believed that the
conduct was necessary to protect himself or herself or another person or as a
reaction to an emergency, and that the conduct itself was an objectively
reasonable response to the circumstances as perceived by the accused.[125]
This test was proposed in recognition of the importance of imposing stringent
controls on the applicability of these defences, if they are extended to
murder.[126]
2.88
In New Zealand there is no requirement that the accused’s belief in the
threat be reasonable, provided it is genuinely held.[127]
2.89
The American Law Institute’s Model Penal Code draft provisions on duress
favour an objective view. The defence is allowed to those who have been
subjected to threats which a person of reasonable firmness in that situation
would have been unable to resist. The words “in his situation” seem to
indicate that certain personal characteristics of the accused should be taken
into account. The commentary on the Model Code indicates that “stark
tangible factors which differentiate the actor from another like his size or
strength or age or health would be considered” although matters of temperament
would not.[128]
In this regard, the Model Penal Code adopts a position very similar to that
currently pertaining in England as outlined in R v Graham.[129]
2.90
It is the settled policy of the criminal law to limit the availability
of the criminal law defences by using an objective test. This prevents
those who lack powers of self control, or who (in the case of duress) may be
particularly cowardly, from obtaining the benefit of them. Clearly the
law should maintain high standards in order to prevent people from giving way
to their fears at the expense of innocent victims.
2.91
However, it has been argued that the law should not enforce
unrealistically high standards of behaviour.[130] The impact of threats which are
visited upon a “weak, immature or disabled” person is much greater. It
has been further suggested that to deny the defence to the “objectively weak”
would be ineffectual as a means of law enforcement.[131]
2.92
Duress differs from other defences such as provocation in that the
defence fails from the beginning if threats of death or serious harm cannot be
established. It has been suggested that if the minimum threshold
requirement of death or serious harm and the reasonable belief element in same
are satisfied, the requirement of reasonable fortitude is superfluous.[132]
2.93
If duress is perceived as excusatory in nature- a concession to human
frailty- then it is arguable that account should be taken of the defendant’s
characteristics. However, it is not appropriate that all of a defendant’s
characteristics should be taken into account as some of these may be morally
repugnant, for example, a practising paedophile who has been threatened with
serious injury unless he has intercourse with a child.[133] It has been suggested that the Graham test can be
perceived as unworkable in practice as it is difficult to determine in advance
what characteristics of the defendant can be taken into consideration.[134]
2.94
However, if duress is to apply to homicide at any stage, it is
imperative that the jury are able to assess the defendant’s actions by
reference to the standards of the ordinary person, and that is certainly a
powerful argument in favour of the requirement.[135] Furthermore it is important that
stringent controls are placed on the applicability of the defence, if it is to
apply to murder, in order to avoid the defence being raised to readily in this
context.
2.95
If a normative standard is preferred, the question remains as to what
personal characteristics of the accused should be attributed to the ordinary
person. The English case law on duress indicates that age, sex, “serious
physical disability” and “medically recognised mental conditions are relevant
considerations.[136] The English Law Commission has
recommended the amendment of the test to provide that the threat or danger was
one “which in all the circumstances (including any of the defendant’s personal
characteristics that affect its gravity) he cannot reasonably be expected to
resist.”[137]
This is essentially a subjective test which would allow particularly weak or
timid defendants who lack ordinary powers of resistance to adduce evidence of
their timidity. The Law Commission has more recently proposed a
recommendation that the defendant’s age and all the circumstances of the
defendant other than those which bear on his capacity to withstand duress
should be relevant for the purpose of the objective test as laid out in R v
Graham.[138]
2.96
The Commission has provisionally concluded in this respect that the line
should be drawn at conditions which affect a defendant’s capacity to resist
threats which would allow the reasonable firmness test to be modified to take
account of various mental conditions while excluding particularly timid or
pliable individuals.
2.97
The Commission provisionally recommends that, in establishing whether
the response of the accused was a reasonable one, an objective test should be
applied.
2.98
The issue to be addressed here is whether the defendant’s belief in the
existence/nature or seriousness of the threat is reasonably held. Yeo
notes:
“As in the case of self-defence, the threat occasion
for the defence of duress may take three possible forms. These are: (i) a
threat occasion which can be objectively demonstrated to have existed; (ii) a
person’s honest albeit reasonable belief as to the existence of a threat
occasion and (iii) a person’s honest and reasonable belief that a threat
occasion existed … It can be stated with confidence that judges and
commentators examining this issue see the choice as being really between the
second and third forms of threat occasions.”[139]
2.99
It is arguable that as a matter of public policy, duress should be
limited in terms of reasonableness and that this extends to the element of
belief in the threats.[140]
However, the law on duress in this regard is not consistent with the law on
provocation and self defence in Ireland.[141]
2.100
The analogy with self defence breaks down on three levels. First, duress
is an excuse and not a justification (like self defence). Thus, society
will not excuse a person who has caused harm to an innocent person by acting on
an unreasonable or negligent belief. Second, in cases of self defence the
decision to retaliate is made in the heat of the moment when the attack is
already underway, which is not necessarily so in situations of duress where the
threat may be imminent but not immediate. Third, it has been suggested
that the reasonableness requirement is out of line with the law on the defence
of mistake since R v Morgan[142] and more recent decisions of the House of Lords, albeit
in the context of proving mens rea for certain sex offences.[143]
2.101
It might be suggested that questions of reasonableness should be a
matter of evidence only which can be accorded due weight by a jury. In
some situations, the more unreasonable the belief, the more likely it is that
it was genuinely held. However it is also true that unreasonable beliefs
can often be blameworthy and “are usually rejected as implausible, fanciful,
disingenuous or the like”.[144]
Further, they may indulge prejudice, for example, a person with racist beliefs
who considers his or her duressor to be violent purely on the grounds of their
race.[145]
2.102
The requirement of reasonably held belief in the existence, nature or
seriousness of the threat can be said to be unnecessary in light of the
requirement that the accused’s response to the threat was reasonable. The
reasonable response requirement does not necessarily mean that a defendant’s
appreciation of the circumstances must also be reasonable, as noted by one
commentator, who goes on to say that “a person who yields to a strong but
imaginary fear may be stupid in imagining it, but he is no more blameworthy
than one whose fear is based on reasonable grounds.”[146]
He further suggests that the opinions of Archbold, Smith and Hogan and of the
Law Commission used by Lord Lane in R v Graham[147]
are in relation to reasonable fortitude, yet lead his Lordship to the policy
statement that appreciation of the factual situation must be reasonable.
2.103
The determination of the conditions which may excuse a defendant who has
acted unlawfully is a distinct, (albeit collateral), issue from mens rea
in which negligence may properly play a role. However, the criminal law
usually does not impose liability on the basis of mere negligence. The
sole requirement that defenders act honestly ensures that liability is not
established by negligence alone.
2.104
In the Commission’s view, a possible solution in this regard is the
position adopted by the Australian courts where the test is what the accused
reasonably believed as opposed to what a reasonable person in the situation
would have believed. The question is therefore not whether an ordinary
person would have held the mistaken belief which the defendant held, but rather
whether an ordinary person with the accused’s characteristics (including
intellectual disability) would have formed such an opinion. This solution
is consistent with the concept of duress as an excuse.[148] The English courts have attempted
to make the objective test a high priority, in order to avoid slipping into the
subjective.
2.105
A further consideration arises if a subjective formulation were to be
adopted. It is possible to distinguish between offences which require
subjective mens rea, such as intention and recklessness, and those which
require a different standard, such as negligence. This argument is advanced
by Howard who suggests that for “offences defined exclusively or primarily in
terms of intention, recklessness or some other subjectively blameworthy states
of mind”, a defence of duress should be judged on the facts as the defendant
took them to be. He then goes on to suggest that for offences not defined
exclusively by these standards a defence of duress should be judged on the
facts as the defendant reasonably took them to be. He added that this
would be subject to the proviso that, in the case of an offence of criminal
negligence, the defendant’s view of the facts should be assessed according to
the same standard of negligence.[149] The Commission concludes that
this is consistent with the current view of the defence of duress.
2.106
The Commission provisionally recommends that the belief in the
existence, nature and seriousness of the threats should be reasonably held and
that the test should be what an ordinary person with the accused’s characteristics
would have reasonably believed in the circumstances.
2.107
Although the requirements of imminence and of official protection are
not synonymous, they are comparable in that if the threat must be imminent, it
will occur before the accused can obtain official protection. The
Commission therefore discusses them together for convenience.
2.108
In Attorney General v Whelan[150] it was noted that the threat must be of
immediate death or serious violence. It was further noted that the
defence of duress will only be available if there was no “reasonable
opportunity for the will [of the defendant] to reassert itself”.
2.109
The requirement of immediacy in duress has been interpreted expansively
in English law so that this element of the defence now equates more precisely
with “imminence”. Similarly, defendants must believe that the threat will
be executed before they can obtain official protection. This requirement
was first laid down in R v McGrowther[151] where Lee CJ noted, in relation to a
charge of treason, that “the only force that doth excuse, is… present fear of
death; and his fear must continue all the time the party remains with the
rebels.”[152]
Modern case law, however, has placed an expansive interpretation on this
requirement.
2.110
In R v Hudson and Taylor,[153] two teenage girls, aged 17 and 19, were
charged with perjury. The defendants admitted giving false evidence at a
criminal trial for assault but pleaded duress, having been threatened with
serious violence by some associates of the accused before the trial. One
of the men who had threatened them was in fact present in the public gallery at
the trial. The trial judge withdrew the defence of duress from the jury
on the grounds that the threats could not have been carried out in a court of
law. The Court of Appeal disagreed. The Court reiterated that the
threat must be effective at the moment when the crime was committed but with
the important qualification that when there was no opportunity for delaying
tactics at the moment of decision, the defence will not fail because the
threatened injury may not follow instantly but after an interval. In other
words the Court of Appeal recognised that a threat can still operate to
neutralise the will of the accused even where they are at that stage free from
the physical control of the person making the threat. The threat must be
imminent but it need not be immediate.
2.111
In relation to the obligation to seek police protection, the Court held
that the defence of duress will not automatically be defeated by a failure to
avail of a reasonable opportunity to render the threat ineffective.
Instead, the reasonableness of a defendant’s conduct should be considered by
the jury in the light of their age, circumstances and the risk involved in so
acting.
2.112
In R v Abdul-Hussain[154] the distinction between immediate and
imminent also arose. In that case, the defendants formed the idea on 8
August 1996 to hijack a plane to avoid being deported to Iraq where they feared
persecution. On 27 August they hijacked a plane at Khartoum airport which
subsequently landed in England where they were charged with offences under the
UK Aviation Security Act 1982. The trial judge
refused to let the defence of duress go to the jury on the basis that the
threat was insufficiently close and immediate to give rise to a spontaneous
reaction to the risk arising. The Court of Appeal quashed the convictions
and held that the trial judge had interpreted the law in this regard too
strictly. The Court confirmed R v Hudson and Taylor and relied on
the distinction between an immediate and an imminent peril noting that “the
peril must operate on the mind of the defendant at the time when he commits the
otherwise criminal act, so as to overbear his will … but the execution of the
threat need not be immediately in prospect.”[155]
2.113
The judgment in R v Hudson and Taylor was referred to in R v
Hasan.[156]
Lord Bingham noted that while he understood that the Court of Appeal in that
case had sympathy with the predicament of the two young girls, he could not
accept that a witness testifying at Manchester Crown Court had no opportunity
to avoid complying with a threat made, the execution of which was not
possible. He noted that the case has had “the unfortunate effect of
weakening the requirement that execution of a threat must be reasonably
believed to be imminent and immediate if it is to support a plea of duress.”[157]
It has been suggested that although R v Hudson and Taylor was not
expressly overruled in R v Hasan, it was “the subject of such
disapproving comment as to effectively render the decision no more than a
historical anomaly.”[158]
2.114
The Law Commission of England and Wales made the following
recommendations in its 1977 Report. First, that the defendant must
believe that the threat will be carried out immediately, or if not immediately,
that there was no real opportunity open to him or her to seek official
protection and that there is no other way of avoiding the harm, and second,
that the effectiveness of the official protection available, in fact or in the
defendant’s belief, is immaterial.[159]
2.115
This recommendation was incorporated into the Law Commission’s Criminal
Code Bill in 1985, with some modifications.[160] For example, the phrase “before
he can obtain official protection” was substituted for “real opportunity of
seeking official protection”, in order to emphasise that the issue was whether
defendants had been able to make actual contact with the authorities rather
than whether they had a chance to look for official assistance.[161]
It is also noteworthy that the 1985 Code questioned the view taken by the Law
Commission as to the efficacy of police protection, although it did not go so
far as to alter the 1977 provisions in this regard.[162]
2.116
In 1989, the Law Commission again referred to this point in its Report
on a Criminal Code.[163]
In line with the 1977 proposals, Clause 42(4) provides that it is immaterial
that the defendant believes that official protection will or may be
ineffective.
2.117
The effectiveness of official protection was one of the specific issues
considered by the Law Commission in its 1993 report, Criminal Law: Legislating
the Criminal Code Offences against the Person and General Principles.[164]
The Law Commission reconsidered its previous position on this aspect of the
defence and recommended the removal of their earlier clause to the effect that
the belief of the accused that the authorities cannot provide adequate
protection should be immaterial. Their reasoning in this regard appears
to be based primarily on a conviction that this would be inconsistent with the
general approach of the rest of the defence. Further, it was noted that
this was the view favoured by the Criminal Code Team, by the Court of Appeal in
R v Hudson and Taylor and by the weight of opinion on consultation.
2.118
The most significant restriction on the operation of the defence in
Canadian law had been the requirement that existed until 2001 that the threat
must be “immediate” and the person making the threats must be “present”.
The Canadian courts interpreted this requirement strictly requiring that the
accused be within the physical control of the duressor at the time the threat
is issued. In R v Carker ( No. 2)[165] the Supreme Court of
Canada rejected duress as a defence to wilful damage by a prison inmate where
threats of bodily harm were made by prisoners locked in separate cells.
This was done on the basis that the threats were neither immediate nor made by
persons actually present. The decision was criticised by Canadian
academics[166]
and was in stark contrast to English law as set out in R v Hudson and
Taylor.[167]
2.119
The requirement was overturned in 2001 in R v Ruzic.[168]
The Supreme Court of Canada held that section 17 of the Canadian Criminal Code,
requiring that the duressor be physically present at the scene of the offence
in order for the defence of duress to be relied upon, was contrary to section 7
of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, by virtue of its restriction in
scope. The Court pointed out that “a threat will seldom meet the
immediacy criterion if the threatener is not physically present at or near the
scene of the offence”[169]
but held that by the strictness of its conditions, section 17 breaches section
7 of the Charter
because it allows individuals who acted involuntarily to be declared criminally
liable.
2.120
In 1982, the Canadian Law Reform Commission had, in a Working Paper on Criminal
Law: The General Part- Liability and Defences, noted that one of the main
difficulties with the law on duress as it stood in Canada was that the
requirement of immediacy arguably rendered superfluous the further requirements
that the accused is not a party to a criminal conspiracy and that the duressor
be present. Therefore in its draft provisions it removed from section 17
the phrase “person who is present when the offence is committed” as in the
Commissions view, in order for the threat of harm to be immediate the harm must
be threatened by a person actually or constructively present.[170]
In its later Report on Recodifying Criminal Law the Canadian Law Reform
Commission also recommended the removal of the need for the threatener’s
presence at the crime. This was justified on the basis that “both are
factors going ultimately to the reasonableness or otherwise of the accused’s
response.”[171]
2.121
The actual presence of the duressor would appear to be a necessary
precondition under the Western Australian and Tasmanian Codes, although not at
common law, or in the other Australian codes.
2.122
Under Australian common law there is no requirement that the
threatener be present at the time the offence is committed.[172] Further, the
threats need not be of immediate harm if all the other requirements, as laid
out in R v Hurley and Murray,[173]
are met.
2.123
The Law Reform Commission of Victoria, in its 1977 Report on Duress, Necessity
and Coercion recommended that the harm need not be immediate, but
imminent and impending, or before the accused could seek official protection,
and the defence remains open to those who believe that such protection would
offer no real protection from the harm.[174] In the 2004 Report on Defences to
Homicide, no reference was made to an immediacy requirement, and the
official protection requirement is covered by the recommendation that the
accused must believe that there is no other way that the threat can be rendered
ineffective other than that action which the accused takes.[175]
2.124
Because the law of duress in New Zealand is so similar to the law in
Canada, the same limitations exist in relation to immediacy as existed in
Canada before R v
Ruzic.[176]
Two of the most significant limitations in the provisions dealing with duress
are found in the requirements in section 21(1) of the Crimes Act 1961
that the threats be of “immediate” harm “from a person who is present when the
offence is committed”. Their importance is highlighted by the fact that
many of the reported cases of compulsion which have come before the Court of
Appeal have failed on one of these grounds.
2.125
In Salaca v The Queen[177] the
defendant claimed that he had committed bigamy in response to a threat from his
prospective wife that if he did not marry her she would get a witch doctor to
do something to him. The Court of Appeal held that there was no
compulsion, despite evidence of the defendant’s belief in the witch doctor’s
supernatural powers, principally on the basis that there was no evidence that
any “immediate” harm was threatened.
2.126
In R v Joyce[178] the
presence requirement proved fatal to the defence. The defendant had
agreed with another person to rob a petrol station but tried to withdraw when
the other person involved revealed that he was going to use a rifle to
accomplish his object. At this point his partner threatened to shoot him
if he did not go through with the plan and the accused complied by acting as
lookout during the robbery. The difficulty arose from the fact that at
the time when the accused was committing the offence, his duressor was inside
the building and it could not be said that he was being threatened by a person
“present”. This is a very strict interpretation of the requirement and
one which operates as a significant limitation on the defence in New
Zealand. As Orchard remarks, the Court’s interpretation of the section
effectively involves reintroducing the word “actually” which had been deleted
from the Criminal Code in 1961.[179]
2.127
Finally, in R v Teichelman[180]
the Court of Appeal confirmed that section 24(1) of the Crimes Act 1961
anticipated situations where the duressor physically “stood over” the accused
while committing the crime:
“The subsection is directed essentially at what are
colloquially called standover situations where the accused fears that instant
death or grievous bodily harm will ensue if he does not do what he is
told. It follows from what we have said that before the matter can go to
a jury there must be evidence of a continuing threat of immediate death or
grievous bodily harm made by a person who is present while the offence is being
committed and so is in a position to carry out the threat or have it carried
out then and there.”
2.128
However, a degree of doubt has been cast upon the validity of the
requirement that the duressor be present at the time of the offence in New
Zealand, as a result of the Canadian case of R v Ruzic.[181]
Because the New Zealand Code is so similar to the Canadian Code, there is a
possibility that this requirement, like its Canadian equivalent, could be
rendered invalid.
2.129
There is no requirement of immediacy or imminence in the American Law
Institute’s Model Penal Code.[182]
2.130
It appears that in general a threat of harm which may not follow
instantly but after an interval will suffice for the defence of duress.
The strict interpretation of this requirement in Canada and New Zealand has
acted as a significant limitation on the operation of the defence in practice
and has attracted considerable academic criticism.[183] The distinction between an
immediate and an imminent threat as drawn by the English Court of Appeal in R
v Hudson and Taylor has been reaffirmed in R v Abdul-Hussain[184] in
which it was held that the threat need only be imminent. It is particularly
significant that in R v
Ruzic[185] the
Supreme Court of Canada has declared that the stringent requirements of
presence and immediacy in the Canadian provisions on duress should be struck
down as contrary to the Canadian Charter of Fundamental Rights. Further,
it is apparent that the pressure that is brought to bear on an accused could be
just as great in cases whether the injury may take place later in time as in
situations where the threat is of immediate injury. The Commission
concurs with the view in R v Abdul-Hussain, that:
“If Anne Frank had stolen a car to escape from
Amsterdam and been charged with theft, the tenets of English law would not, in
our judgment, have denied her a defence of duress of circumstances, on the
ground that she should have waited for the Gestapo’s knock on the door.”[186]
2.131
The requirement that the defendant must avail of any official protection
open to him or her poses the further question of whether a defendant’s
subjective belief in the ineffectiveness of the authorities should give rise to
liability. The Law Reform Commission of Victoria has linked the question
of immediacy to the issue of resort to official protection by recommending a
formulation that “the person believed that the harm threatened was likely to
occur immediately if the person threatened did not take the action in question
or if not immediately before he could have any real opportunity of seeking
official protection”.[187]
Thus, the existence of a reasonable avenue of escape would mean that the threat
could not be considered imminent.
2.132
In the Commission’s view a person’s belief that he or she cannot be protected
goes to the heart of the issue surrounding his or her freedom of action.
This approach is consistent with the underlying rationale of the approach to
act as a concession to human frailty.
2.133
It is true that in some circumstances, for example, domestic violence,
official protection may well prove ineffective. In the Commission’s view,
however, it should not be left solely to the jury to consider whether the
defendant believed the protection would be effective. This would involve
difficult collateral issues, which may be very broad in scope and there is also
a significant danger of misuse of the defence.
2.134
The Commission has concluded in this respect that it is essential that
the defence of duress should not be used as a means of undermining the laws on
perjury and contempt of court. A normative approach would nearly always
preclude the defence in situations where a person is compelled to commit
perjury.
2.135
The Commission provisionally recommends that while the threat should
be imminent, no requirement of immediacy should exist in relation to the harm
threatened.
2.136
The Commission provisionally recommends that the person threatened
should be required to seek official protection if possible but that a failure
to do so will not automatically preclude the availability of the defence.
2.137
The defence of duress is generally regarded as not being available to
defendants who have knowingly exposed themselves to the threat, for example, by
voluntarily joining a criminal organisation which subsequently puts pressure on
them to commit offences. This is an important limitation on the defence
in practice.
2.138
There does not appear to be any Irish authority on this issue and Attorney
General v Whelan[188]
makes no reference to it.
2.139
In R v Hasan,[189] the
question put forward for consideration by the House of Lords on appeal was as
follows:
“Whether the defence of duress is excluded when, as
a result of the accused’s voluntary association with others:
(i) he foresaw (or possibly
should have foreseen) the risk of being subjected to any compulsion by
threats of violence;
(ii) only when he foresaw (or
should have foreseen) the risk of being subjected to compulsion to commit
criminal offences; and, if the latter;
(iii) only if the offences foreseen (or
which should have been foreseen) were of the same type (or possibly of
the same type and gravity) as that ultimately committed.” [190]
2.140
Lord Bingham rejected the defendant’s argument that options (ii) and
(iii) were correct holding that “nothing should turn on foresight of the manner
in which, in the event, the dominant party chooses to exploit the defendant’s
subservience.”[191]
It was held that the defence of duress is excluded when, as a result of the
accused’s voluntary association with others engaged in criminal activity, he
foresaw, or ought reasonably to have foreseen, the risk of being subjected to any
compulsion by threats of violence.[192]
2.141
The House of Lords in R v Hasan relied on a number of authorities
on this point, the first of which is the decision of the Northern Ireland Court
of Appeal in R v Fitzpatrick.[193]
In R v Fitzpatrick,
the accused pleaded duress to a robbery charge on the basis that the IRA had
forced him to commit the crime. He had voluntarily joined the IRA some
years previously. The Court rejected his defence on the basis that a
defendant who has recklessly exposed himself to the risk of being subjected to
coercive pressure forfeits the right to invoke duress in order to “put on when
it suits him the breastplate of righteousness.” Indeed, if the Court had
accepted the defence, then the better organised the conspiracy and the more
brutal its internal discipline, the more confident members of the group may be
of relying on the defence of duress and it could hardly be supposed that the
criminal law tolerates such an absurdity. This principle was extended in R
v Calderwood and Moore[194] to a
situation where the accused claimed he did not join the organisation
voluntarily but had voluntarily associated with a group of people who were
engaged in criminal and violent activities. The Court reasoned that he
had thereby exposed himself to the risk of compulsion to join the group and the
concomitant risk of compulsion to commit criminal acts.
2.142
In R v Sharp[195] the
defendant was part of a group who carried out a series of armed robberies on
sub post offices. He claimed that he panicked when he saw that guns were
to be used in the course of one robbery and expressed a desire to withdraw, but
another one of the robbers threatened to “blow his head off” if he did not
carry on with the plan. In the course of the robbery a postmaster was
killed by one of the robbers. Sharp was convicted of manslaughter and
appealed. The Court of Appeal relied on the opinions of the Law Lords in DPP
for Northern Ireland v Lynch[196] in reaching the conclusion that persons who voluntarily
place themselves in a situation where they are likely to be subject to
compulsion cannot subsequently avail of the defence of duress. Although
the point did not arise directly in Lynch, their Lordships
did express the view obiter
that the prior fault of a defendant in placing themselves in a situation
where they could be exposed to duress would defeat duress. The appeal in Sharp
was accordingly rejected.
2.143
The harshness of this rule was alleviated somewhat by the subsequent
decision in R v Shepherd.[197] In
that case the appellant was a member of a shoplifting gang. After a
number of such outings, he wanted to give it up but was threatened with
violence to himself and his family by another member of the gang. The
Court of Appeal held that his conviction should be overturned as duress had not
been left to the jury. Mustill LJ stated:
“Common sense must recognise that there are certain
kinds of criminal enterprises the joining of which, in the absence of any knowledge
of propensity to violence on the part of one member, would not lead another to
suspect that a decision to think better of the whole affair might lead him into
serious trouble.”[198]
2.144
Thus, it appears that the defence is not automatically denied to
defendants who have voluntarily allied themselves with the persons exercising
the duress. The Court will assess the defendant’s knowledge of the
methods of the gang and of its members in deciding whether to allow the defence
to go to the jury.
2.145
The Law Commission recommended in its 1977 draft provisions on duress
that the defence should not be available where the defendant is voluntarily and
without reasonable cause in a situation in which he or she knows he or she will
or may be subjected to duress.[199] This recommendation was not
repeated in the Commission’s later 1993 Report in which it was noted that such
a limitation was consistent with case law and its earlier recommendations.[200]
2.146
In the more recent Law Commission Consultation Paper A New Homicide
Act for England and Wales?,[201] the Law Commission noted that in the light of the recent
case of R v Hasan,[202]
the issue of voluntary exposure to duress has been resolved, and it is quite
clear now that a person who has voluntarily exposed himself or herself to
duress will be precluded from relying on the defence.[203]
2.147
Under the Canadian Criminal Code, the defence of duress is not available
to those who have voluntarily exposed themselves to the risk of duress.
The defence is limited to those who are not “a party to a conspiracy or
association whereby the person is subject to compulsion.”[204] However, the phrase “party to a
conspiracy or association whereby he is subject to compulsion” can be
interpreted to refer to group activity wider than membership of a criminal
gang, and would probably extend to the lesser level of association at issue in
the Northern Irish decision of R v Calderwood and Moore.[205]
2.148
As already noted in relation to immediacy, the Canadian Law Reform
Commission has suggested that this requirement renders superfluous the
requirement that the accused is not a party to a criminal conspiracy.
Therefore, in the draft provision the words “if he is not a party to a
conspiracy” were omitted, with the result that where the harm threatened is
immediate, duress will be a defence even if the accused has subjected himself
to the risk of duress.[206]
It is also noteworthy that the later report in 1987 dispensed with the need for
the accused’s absence from conspiracy, based on the view that it was a factor
going to the reasonableness of the accused’s response.[207]
2.149
One of the requirements laid out in R v Hurley and Murray[208] was
that the accused can only avail of the defence if he or she did not expose him
or herself to the threat by his or her own volition.
2.150
There is disparity between the common law and the Codes in relation to
the issue of self induced duress. While the general principle that the
protection of the defence does not extend to those who expose themselves to the
risk of duress is common to all the States, the Code provisions are more
stringent than common law. It would appear that none of the Codes, except
for the ACT and Commonwealth Codes, require subjective appreciation of the
risk, although it has been noted that “it is possible to construe the words
‘enter into’ and ‘by being a party’ as referring only to willing or voluntary
participants.”[209]
2.151
The 1977 Report of the Law Reform Commission of Victoria, in its draft
provisions, recommended that the defence would not apply if the actor
voluntarily, and without reasonable cause, placed himself in the situation when
he believed he might be called on to commit the offence, or a similar offence.[210]
In the Commission’s later Report on Defences to Homicide it recommended
that duress should not be available to those who are threatened by or on behalf
of a person with whom the accused is voluntarily associating for the purpose of
carrying out conduct of the kind carried out. This avoids the possibility
of the defence being used by those who kill in the course of criminal activity,
and is in line with the ACT and Commonwealth Criminal Codes. [211]
2.152
In R v Joyce[212]
the Court of Appeal noted that a literal interpretation of section 24(1) of the
Crimes Act 1961 that the accused “is not a party to any association or
conspiracy whereby he is subject to compulsion” would remove the defence from
any accused who was a party to any association or conspiracy. But, in
that case the Court of Appeal held that this limitation was contingent on
whether violence was reasonably foreseeable. The test is therefore
whether “the very nature of the association was such that the offender as a
reasonable man should have been able to foresee that the association was of a
kind that at least rendered it possible that at a later stage he might be made
subject to compulsion”.
2.153
Should the fact that a defendant ought reasonably to have foreseen the likelihood
of being subjected to threats disbar him or her from the defence or should
actual foresight of the risk of compulsion be required?
2.154
It should be reiterated that a defendant who should have availed of a
reasonable opportunity to escape the threats cannot seek to rely on the
defence. Similarly, the defence is not available where the defendant has
voluntarily allied himself with his threateners. The objective/subjective
dichotomy also arises in relation to this aspect of the defence - namely,
whether the defendant should be held liable on the basis of his personal
knowledge of the risk or whether the defence can be denied where the defendant
negligently omitted to perceive the propensity of a criminal gang to
violence. In many ways the answer to this question follows on from the
analogous issue of resort to official protection, as both have in common that
the accused had been culpable in allowing the development of the duress.
It also bears similarities to the question of reasonable belief, discussed
above in relation to the effect of the threat and the defendant’s perception
thereof.[213]
2.155
The essential question is whether there should be a test based on
foresight, which centres on whether the defendant had placed himself in a
situation where he or she knows that he or she will be subjected to duress in
the future. In the Commission’s view this is properly a matter of fact
for the jury. As Elliott has pointed out, stupid or particularly naive
defendants should not be punished on account of their stupidity. The
defendant is no more blameworthy than one whose opinion on the risk of duress
has been formed on reasonable grounds.[214]
2.156
Another argument against a test based on foresight is that those who
have failed to perceive signals which would alert the ordinary individual to
the risk of violence are culpable and should not be allowed to escape
liability. As a matter of public policy, the Commission concurs with the
view that duress should be limited in terms of reasonableness.
2.157
On the other hand, the Commission acknowledges that society requires a
person who joins a criminal organisation to take reasonable care as to the use
of violence. A failure to do this should disqualify a defendant from the
defence.[215]
2.158
Denying the defence on the grounds that society expects those in a
criminal organisation to take reasonable care may act as an added incentive to
defendants to escape from the criminal organisation (in addition to the
requirement that the defendant must avail of any official protection open to
him or her.)[216]
2.159
The Commission provisionally recommends that a person who seeks to
avail of the defence of duress may not do so if they ought reasonably to have
foreseen the likelihood of being subjected to threats, for example, by
voluntarily joining a criminal organisation which subsequently
puts pressure on the person to commit offences.
2.160
In this section, the Commission deals with marital coercion, a special
defence that was afforded to a married woman who had committed certain crimes
in the presence of her husband. This is discussed in the context of
duress as it is connected with the defence of duress and its development is
certainly linked with the defence of duress. Under the defence of marital
coercion, it was presumed that if a woman’s husband was present then she had
acted under his immediate coercion unless the prosecution could prove that she
took the initiative in committing the offence. This defence should be
distinguished from the defences of duress and necessity which are of general
application. It did not extend to the offences of treason or murder, nor
to brothel-keeping as this latter offence was believed to pertain to the governance
of the home.
2.161
It would appear that the presumption was first developed in the Middle
Ages to mitigate the effects of the rule denying the benefit of clergy to
women.[217]
However, the benefit of clergy was in fact extended to women in 1692 and it has
been suggested that the rule has survived for at least twelve centuries.[218]
2.162
The law in this country in relation to the presumption of marital
coercion was put beyond doubt in the case of State (DPP) v Walsh and
Conneely[219],
a contempt case which arose out of the well known capital murder case of People
(DPP) v Murray[220].
The Murrays had been sentenced to death by the Special Criminal Court.
The two defendants, Walsh and Conneely, were members of an organisation called
the Association for Legal Justice and had issued a press statement commenting
on the Special Criminal Court's trial and conviction of the Murrays. The
statement commented that the Special Criminal Court lacked judicial
independence and that, in trying the Murrays, it had “so abused the rules of
evidence as to make the court akin to a sentencing tribunal”. The
defendants were tried for contempt and convicted and they then appealed to the
Supreme Court. The issue of marital coercion was raised as the second
named accused claimed that the statement referring to the Court as a sentencing
tribunal was inserted in the article at her husband’s suggestion.
2.163
Henchy J held that the facts were clearly capable of rebutting the
presumption of coercion but noted that in any event the doctrine was no longer
extant in the State. He noted that the raison d’etre for the
rule “had been swept away by legislation and judicial decisions” and that the
presumption “presupposes a disparity in status and capacity between husband and
wife which runs counter to the normal relations between a married couple in
modern times.” Most significantly, however, he held that the rule had not
survived the enactment of the Constitution as it offended the concept of
equality before the law in Article 40.1:
“A legal rule that presumes, even on a prima
facie and rebuttable basis, that a wife has been coerced by the physical
presence of her husband into committing an act prohibited by the criminal law,
particularly when a similar presumption does not operate in favour of a husband
for acts committed in the presence of his wife, is repugnant to the concept of
equality before the law guaranteed by the first sentence of Article 40, s 1,
and could not, under the second sentence of that Article, be justified as a
discrimination based on any difference of capacity or of social function as
between husband and wife. Therefore, the presumption contended for must
be rejected as being a form of unconstitutional discrimination.”
2.164
It is clear that the decision in State (DPP) v Walsh and
Conneely is that the defence of marital coercion did not survive the
enactment of the Constitution. This would preclude the enactment of a
statutory defence of marital coercion similar to that which exists in England.
2.165
Abolition of the presumption of marital coercion was advocated as early
as 1845.[221]
The complete abolition of the defence - with the result that wives would be
placed in the same position as other defendants - was recommended by the Avory
Committee,[222]
and this was implemented by section 47 of the Criminal Justice Act 1925 which provides:
“Any presumption of the law that an offence
committed by a wife in the presence of her husband is committed under the
coercion of the husband is hereby abolished, but on a charge against a wife for
any offence other than treason or murder, it shall be a good defence to prove
that the offence was committed in the presence of, and under the coercion of,
the husband.”
2.166
The result of this provision seems to be that a wife may still use the
defence of marital coercion, but the burden of proof is on her to prove, on the
balance of probabilities, that she was subject to coercion. However the
provision has caused some interpretation problems, the question being whether
this statutory defence is in fact a synonym for the defence of duress or
whether it constitutes something wider than duress. It has been noted
that during the parliamentary debate surrounding the enactment of the
legislation, opinion was expressed that coercion included moral and spiritual,
not just, physical coercion, thereby allowing the new statutory defence to
constitute something wider than duress. However, if coercion were to mean
something more than duress, it appears odd that it would not be defined as such
in the legislation.[223]
2.167
In R v Shortland[224] it
was held that the wife must prove that her will was overborne by the wishes of
her husband, and that there was no need for proof of physical force or the
threat of physical force, for the proof of moral force would suffice. In
this case, the court referred to R v Richmond and Richmond[225]
in which it was also found that moral coercion would suffice. Coercion is
thus a wider defence than duress and in fact is available to wives in addition
to that general defence.
2.168
While the rationale for granting a wider defence to wives appears to be
that a wife needs this extra protection, the Avory Committee of 1922 was not of
this opinion, and Stephen points out that it is quite absurd to allow more
protection to a wife than to a daughter of 15.[226]
2.169
Williams points out that two parts of the old law retain their
significance in the new statutory defence. First, the defence is
available only to a “wife”, but he notes that it is not necessary for a
marriage to be strictly proved.[227] However, in R v Ditta, Hussain
and Kara,[228] the court found that the man and woman must be husband and
wife in the strict sense of the terms. Second, the crime must have been
committed in the presence of the husband, though the interpretation of this has
been loose enough to allow a wife to plead the defence even when the husband
was not in the same room.[229]
2.170
The abolition of the defence was recommended by the Law Commission in
its 1977 Report on Defences of General Application.[230] There were several reasons for
this, including the following:
· There
are uncertainties surrounding the operation of the defence, for example, in
relation to the strictness of the requirement in law that the husband be
physically present when the wife commits the offence;
· There
are very few instances of the defence being invoked;
· The
defence is ill-suited to modern conditions. Many married women are now
financially independent from their husbands;
· It
is absurd to provide a special defence to wives which is not available to other
women who may be placed in an equally vulnerable position, such as a woman
living with a man as his common law wife, or a dependant daughter of 17 years.
2.171
As yet however, no move has been made to abolish this defence in
England, which has been described by some as a “relic of the past which ought
to have been abolished long ago.”[231]
2.172
The common law presumption of coercion has been abolished in the
majority of common law jurisdictions, many of which now seem to place the wife
in the same position as other accused persons.
2.173
The presumption was abolished in Canada as far back as 1892 with the
enactment of the first Criminal Code.[232] In the Canadian Law Reform
Commissions 1982 Working Paper,[233] it was noted that draft legislation to
recodify the criminal law should omit the reference to the fact that no
presumption of marital coercion exists, on the basis that the old common law
rule had been abolished in the Criminal Code, and it would not be relevant to
mention it in a revised code. In the later Report on Recodifying Criminal
Law there was no mention of the presumption, or its abolition. [234]
2.174
The common law presumption of marital coercion was abolished in New
Zealand by section 44 of the Crimes Act 1908, as
amended by s24 Crimes
Act 1961.
2.175
There is some disparity in the Australian states in relation to their
treatment of the presumption of marital coercion. New South Wales was the first
state to abolish the rule in 1900[235] and created in its
place a rule similar to the English defence. Victoria abolished the
presumption in 1958, and also created a similar defence to the English one.[236]
This statutory
defence is not subject to the interpretation difficulties of the English one
however.[237]
Queensland and Western Australia have followed suit, abolishing the rule by
legislation, and replacing it with a similar rule. South Australia, in 1935,
abolished the rule and created a defence of coercion identical to the English
provisions.[238]
Therefore the
defence remains but the presumption is removed. In the Australian Capital
Territory, the presumption has also been abolished.[239] In the Northern Territory the defence has
remained at common law.
2.176
In the United States, a dwindling number of states continue to adhere to
the marital rule. Boyce and Perkins note that:
“it is definitely not recognised in the overwhelming
majority of jurisdictions … The presumption of coercion arising from the mere
presence of the husband is usually not as strong as formerly, even where still
recognised. It is a mistake, however, to assume that the ‘doctrine of
coercion’ has disappeared entirely.”[240]
2.177
Section 2.09 of the Model Penal Code, which treats the defence of
duress, provides that: “It is not a defense that a woman acted on the command
of her husband, unless she acted under such coercion as would establish a
defense under this Section. [The presumption that a woman, acting in the
presence of her husband, is coerced is abolished].”
2.178
While the appropriateness of the retention of a defence of marital
coercion is debatable, there have been suggestions that the defence is in
actual fact still in existence in the form of Battered Woman Syndrome
(BWS). It has been noted that just as marital coercion vanished in the
mid 1970’s, it re-emerged in the guise of BWS.[241] While BWS is not in itself a
defence, it has in some cases been considered a species of duress, and has been
found to be relevant to defences such as duress, provocation and self-defence.[242]One
commentator suggests however that BWS is more similar to the marital coercion
standard rather than the duress standard. It has been noted that a
woman’s conduct may have been unreasonable but she is excused from liability if
she can prove that her choices were determined not by her own will, but by the
“superior will of her husband.”[243] It is more likely that BWS could
be used to support the defence of duress and show that there existed a genuine
threat and fear, rather than the syndrome itself being used as a defence.
2.179
In most jurisdictions the presumption of marital coercion has been
abolished on the basis that it is archaic, and no longer necessary. Boyce
and Perkins note that “[T]here may have been some reason for this doctrine in
the ancient law but there is none today.”[244] As noted above the comments
of Henchy J in State (DPP) v Walsh and Conneely preclude
the enactment in Ireland of a provision similar to that pertaining in
England. In any case, there appears to be few policy grounds on which
such a change in the law could be supported, or indeed which support the
retention of the provision in other jurisdictions. Pace does argue that
there is a legitimate need for a “defence which recognises the peculiar and
particular vulnerability of married women to pressure from their husbands”[245]
while Williams observed in 1961 that “there are some who hold that the wife
still needs wider protection than other people, on the ground that something of
her former subordination to her husband still survives in social mores.” The
latter author was, however, quick to point out that the Commissions of 1845 and
1922 did not adhere to this view.[246] The argument retains even less
force today. Howard describes the rule as “an anachronism of no apparent
value.”[247]
2.180
Furthermore, the legislative trend in most common law jurisdictions is
to place wives who come before the criminal courts in the same position as
other defendants. The Commission agrees that this is correct and that the
defence of marital coercion is indeed an anachronism in today’s society and
should be formally abolished by statute to reflect the analysis in State
(DPP) v Walsh and Conneely. Of course, the defence of duress will
remain open to a wife who is threatened by her husband, and even where such
threats fall short of the requirements of the defence, they will form an
important part of any plea for mitigation on her behalf.
2.181
The Commission provisionally recommends that the defence of marital
coercion should be formally abolished by statute, and notes that the defence of
duress is available to any person who is threatened by their spouse or partner.
2.182
In The People (DPP) v Kavanagh[248] the Court of Criminal Appeal confirmed that, as with
other defences, the onus at all times lies with the prosecution to disprove the
defence of duress beyond a reasonable doubt. The defendant had only to
discharge the evidential burden in relation to the defence by placing such
evidence before the Court as made the issue fit and proper to be left to the
jury.
2.183
It was held by the Court of Criminal Appeal that:
“[i]t is of course
clear that it is no part of the duty of a defendant in any criminal case to
prove a defence. The onus is at all times on the Director of Public
Prosecutions to prove every ingredient of the crime alleged against the accused
beyond reasonable doubt.”
The Court went on to refer to Archbold[249] which notes that the evidential burden
is on the defendant and having done this, the persuasive burden is on the
prosecution to “destroy the defence in such a manner as to leave in the minds
of the jury no reasonable doubt on the question whether the defendant can be
absolved on the ground of the alleged compulsion.”
2.184
The issue was considered again in The People (DPP) v Dickey.[250] The trial judge had directed the jury that where
the issue of duress has having been raised by the defence, it is incumbent on
the prosecution to rebut the issue. The Court of Criminal Appeal held
that the jury may not have been fully aware that there was a burden of proof on
the prosecution to prove that the applicant was not acting under duress, rather
than to rebut the defence that he was so acting. It was also noted by the
Court that the jury may not have been aware that the standard of proof in such
a rebuttal is beyond reasonable doubt. The appeal was therefore allowed
and the Court ordered a retrial.
2.185
In 1993, the Law Commission of England and Wales[251] recommended that the burden of proof be
reversed, placing the burden on the defendant, on the balance of probabilities,
to establish the defence of duress and also to show, if necessary, that they
did not knowingly and without reasonable excuse expose themselves to the risk
of the threat being made. The reasons offered for this change were,
first, that applying the defence to murder would be more palatable if the
burden were reversed; second, it would be difficult for the prosecution to
disprove the defence in certain cases, for example where the defendants may
have been members of a gang; and third, that the defence is unique and the circumstances
leading to the threat may have occurred quite separately from the commission of
the crime and thus it would be particularly difficult for the prosecution to
disprove.
2.186
It has been suggested that none of these reasons are convincing enough
to lead to a reversal of the burden of proof in relation to duress.
First, it is not clear whether the application of the defence of duress to
murder is appropriate,[252]
so reversing the burden for that purpose is not necessary. Second, the
burden was reversed in order to “concentrate … on the plausibility of the
defendant’s story”[253]
and it has been suggested that reversing the burden would thus entail a shift
from the adversarial system of trial to an inquisitorial approach, which would
affect the presumption of innocence. Third, it has been noted that the
“uniqueness” of the defence does not affect problems of proof which may arise
in establishing or refuting the facts.
2.187
In a recent case referring to the burden of proof (involving the defence
of diminished responsibility), R v McQuade,[254]
the issue of reverse burdens of proof was discussed. In that case Kerr LCJ
made reference to the conjoined appeals of Sheldrake v DPP,
Attorney-General’s Reference (No 4 of 2004)[255] in
which Lord Bingham gave considerable attention to the issue. It was noted
by Lord Bingham that UK law prior to the incorporation of the European
Convention on Human Rights under the Human Rights Act 1998 regarded the principle that the onus lies on the
prosecution in a criminal trial to prove all the elements of an offence as
supremely important, but not absolute. He went on to note that Parliament
has been prepared in some instances to impose legal burdens on, or provide for
presumptions rebuttable by, the defendant. He also noted that although
the presumption of innocence has not been treated as absolute by Parliament,
the underlying rationale has been that “it is repugnant to ordinary notions of
fairness for a prosecutor to accuse a defendant of crime and for the defendant
to be then required to disprove the accusation on pain of conviction and punishment
if he fails to do so.”
2.188
In R v McQuade, the defendant contended that section 5(3) of the Criminal
Justice Act (Northern Ireland) 1966, which provided that
it was for the defence to prove (on the balance of probabilities, pursuant to
section 5(4)) that the defendant suffered from a mental abnormality, was
incompatible with the presumption of innocence guaranteed by Article 6(2) of
the European Convention on Human Rights. It was held that while the
defendant in this case must establish the proposition on the balance of
probabilities, it does not, in the circumstances, seem reasonable that the
prosecution (facing a higher standard of proof) should be burdened with such
difficulties in evidence that may arise from this lack of certainty. The
Court went on to note that this conclusion was reached due to the practical
difficulties involved in proving that a person who raises the issue of mental
abnormality does not suffer from that condition.
2.189
In R v Hasan,[256]
Lord Bingham affirmed that the burden is on prosecution to establish that the
defendant did not commit the crime with which he is charged under duress.
He went on to refer to the Law Commission’s recommendation that the burden be
reversed, noting that even if the House were convinced of the merits of such a
reversal, there would be doubt as to whether the House, in its judicial
capacity, could make such a change. He went on to note that the
Commission was correct in its statement that the defence of duress is
peculiarly difficult for the prosecution to investigate and disprove beyond
reasonable doubt.[257]
Notwithstanding this, it remains unclear whether Parliament would be prepared
to reverse the burden, thus placing the burden of proof on the defendant, and
putting limitations on the presumption of innocence.
2.190
In a recent Law Commission Consultation Paper, A New Homicide Act for
England and Wales?,[258] the Law Commission reconsidered and indicated that
reversing the burden could still be an option. However, the Law
Commission is keen to point out that it is no longer the case that one can
claim that duress is an easy defence to raise and a difficult one to
disprove. It is noted that recent changes in the law mean that it is no
longer necessary to recommend that the defendant bear the burden of proof and
ultimately the Commission appear to accept the view expressed in R v Hasan that
there is no need to place a reverse burden on the defendant.
2.191
The Commission considers that the recent views expressed by the Court of
Criminal Appeal in the Kavanagh and Dickey cases are consistent
with the appropriate roles of the prosecution and defence, both in terms of
traditional common law principles and human rights principles. The
Commission therefore provisionally recommends that the burden of proof as it
stands, with the onus on the prosecution to disprove the defence beyond a reasonable
doubt, is appropriate.
2.192
The Commission provisionally recommends that the onus should remain
on the prosecution to disprove the defence of duress beyond a reasonable doubt.
3.01
In Chapter 2, the Commission discussed the general scope of and
limitations to the defence of duress. In this Chapter, the Commission
discusses whether the defence should apply, either as a full or partial defence, to murder.
3.02
As already noted, the only modern Irish case which has examined the
scope of the defence of duress is Attorney General v. Whelan.[259]
3.03
The decision in Whelan
concerned a charge of receiving stolen property. However the Court added,
obiter, that “[t]he commission of murder is a crime so heinous that [it]
should not be committed even for the price of life and in such a case the
strongest duress would not be any justification”.[260] This view reflected the
contemporary view of the scope of the defence, namely that while it applied to
many offences, it was generally not applicable to murder. This aspect of
the judgment has been approved in a number of cases in other jurisdictions.[261]
3.04
The dicta in Whelan represent the only judicially expressed view
in Ireland on the application (or non-application, more correctly) of duress to
murder. Indeed, given that the dicta refer to murder, it can be argued
that the Court did not consider whether there may be other forms of homicide to
which the defence does apply. There has been considerable
discussion of the application of the defence to murder in various other
jurisdictions. The Commission therefore considers it is appropriate to
discuss those more recent developments in the context of this Consultation
Paper.
3.05
It is now generally accepted in English law that duress is available as
a defence to all crimes except for murder, attempted murder, and some forms of
treason.[262]
3.06
In the landmark decision of R v Howe[263]
the House of Lords stated categorically that duress was not available on a
charge of murder or aiding or abetting murder.
3.07
The argument for excluding murder from the ambit of the defence can be
traced back to Hale[264]
who wrote:
“Again, if a man be desperately assaulted, and in
peril of death, and cannot otherwise escape, unless to satisfy his assailant’s
fury he will kill an innocent person then present, the fear and actual force
will not acquit him of the crime and punishment of murder, if he commit the fact;
for he ought rather to die himself, than kill an innocent.”
3.08
Blackstone[265]
echoed Hale’s remarks in stating that “ a
man ought rather to die himself than escape by the murder of an
innocent”. However, as observed by some commentators, the authority
supporting Hale and other writers on this point appears weak.[266]
In this regard it has been noted that “[a]lthough Hale’s famous statement is
now regarded as authoritative, neither its connection with early modern case
law nor its impact on nineteenth century jurisprudence was impressively firm”.[267]
3.09
The uncertain state of the law in this area was perhaps borne out by the
emergence of authority to the effect that accomplices to murder could avail of
the defence. In R v Kray (Ronald)[268] the
Court of Appeal accepted that an accessory before the fact to murder had a
viable defence in claiming that by reason of threats he was so terrified that
he ceased to be an independent actor. The case concerned a man who had
carried a gun from one place to another, knowing that the defendant intended to
use it for murder.
3.10
The decision in Kray
was cited with approval in DPP for Northern Ireland v
Lynch[269]
where the majority of the House of Lords allowed the defence of duress to an
alleged principal in the second degree to murder. The defendant had been
threatened by members of the IRA and forced to drive them to a place where a
policeman was shot. He then drove the killers away from the scene.
When interviewed, he said that he was certain that if he disobeyed the IRA
members he would be killed and so he had no choice but to drive the car.
The trial judge decided not to leave the defence of duress to the jury on the
ground that it was not available on a charge of murder as a matter of law. The
Northern Ireland Court of Appeal upheld this view by a two to one
majority.
3.11
In the House of Lords, it was held, by a majority of 3-2, that on a
charge of murder, the defence of duress was available to a person charged in
the second degree. Lord Wilberforce examined the rationale referred to in
Attorney General v Whelan for excluding murder from the defence, namely,
that murder was a most heinous crime. He nonetheless held that that does
not preclude the defence operating in respect of all cases of murder
and he concluded that: “[A]n accessory before the fact, or an aider and
abettor, may (not necessarily must) bear a less degree [of heinousness] than
the actual killer: and even if the rule of exclusion is absolute, or nearly so
in relation to the latter, it need not be so in lesser cases.”[270]
3.12
Lynch has
been criticised, however, on this very point, namely, that a principal in the
second degree on a murder charge, may be just as, if not more, morally culpable
than the actual perpetrator. For example, when the matter was revisited
in R v Abbott,[271]
the majority of the Privy Council distinguished Lynch and decided that
the defence was not available to a principal to murder where the defendant was
alleged to have actively taken part in the killing of the deceased, holding her
while she was stabbed, and assisting in burying her while she was still
alive. The minority, however, approved Lynch in holding that
the defence should be allowed, arguing that it was inconsistent to allow duress
to aiders and abettors but not to principals in the first degree. This
inconsistency was resolved in R v Howe[272]
where the House
of Lords took the opportunity to re-examine the law.
3.13
In R v Howe, the House of Lords opted to restore the law to its
pre-Lynch
position. Lord Hailsham was strongly influenced by the well-known decision
in R v Dudley and Stephens[273] which held that the defence of
necessity (arising from imminent danger not caused by human threats) did not
apply to murder.[274]
While Lord Hailsham conceded that there was a distinction to be drawn between
duress and necessity in relation to the origin of the danger, he considered
that this distinction was irrelevant, since duress, was only the specific type
of necessity caused by wrongful threats. He considered the argument that
this approach was to expect heroism of ordinary individuals, but he concluded
that:
“in general I do not accept in relation to the
defence of duress it is either good morals, good policy or good law as did the
majority in Lynch
and the minority in Abbott
that an ordinary man of reasonable fortitude is not to be supposed to be
capable of heroism if he is asked to take an innocent life rather than
sacrifice his own.”
3.14
Lord Griffiths took a similar approach. He felt that the reason
the defence of necessity was denied in Dudley was the same
reason that duress must be denied as a defence to murder, namely, the special
sanctity which the law attaches to human life and which denies the right to a
person to take an innocent life even at the price of one’s own or another’s
life. Lord Griffiths also said that he could find no clear basis on which
to differentiate between various participants in murder, and on that basis he
disagreed with the majority in Lynch.
3.15
The English Law Commission[275] has identified the following 4
arguments advanced by the House of Lords in Howe in support of
their conclusions:
· Since
Hale’s time it has been understood that the law provides no defence of duress
to murder. This is in line with the defence of necessity;
· The
sanctity which the law attaches to human life requires that it lay down such
standards of conduct;
· It
was noted that the social climate at the time, with its “rising tide of
violence and terrorism”[276]
was not an appropriate time for change;
· In
the more difficult cases, the proper exercise of prosecutorial discretion can
mitigate the effects of the rule. Further, the Home Secretary and the
Parole Board may take the circumstances of the murder into account when
considering parole, and this can mitigate the rigours of a blanket denial of
the defence.
3.16
The law in relation to attempted murder was put beyond all doubt by a
majority of the House of Lords in R v Gotts[277] where
it was held that the defence of duress was not applicable to attempted
murder. This seems to be a logical extension of Howe given that
attempted murder requires an intention to kill, not simply to injure seriously.
3.17
As noted above, the defence of duress has always been deemed to be
excluded from some forms of treason. In this regard, Hale[278]
suggests that the defence could be pleaded on a charge of treason during
wartime but not in peacetime on the basis that in peacetime “the law hath
provided a sufficient remedy against such fears by applying himself to the
courts and officers of justice for a writ or precept de securitatae pacis.”[279]
Williams[280]
also argues for a limitation on the availability of the defence where the
treason “takes the form of endangering hundreds or thousands of lives” on the
basis that such actions could not be justified on the basis of personal fears.
3.18
A survey of the relevant old case law, however, reveals that in a
majority of the cases involving treason the defence would appear to have been
allowed.[281]
More recently, in R v Purdy[282] the
court allowed a claim of fear of death as a defence to a British prisoner of
war charged with treason by assisting the Germans with propaganda during the
Second World War.
3.19
As against this, in R v Axtell[283]
(“the Regicides case”) the court rejected a claim by the accused that as
soldiers they would themselves have been executed for disobedience if they had
failed to execute Charles I. However, it is arguable that while the
charge in form was one of treason, it was in substance one of murder, and, as
such, duress could not be allowed.[284]
3.20
The Law Commission of England and Wales has examined the issue of duress
on several occasions. The Law Commission first published a Working Paper
on duress and other defences in 1974[285] and after a consultation process,
presented its Report in July 1977.[286]
3.21
The Law Commission had little difficulty in deciding to recommend that
duress should be retained as a defence. It was noted that the murder exception
rule was inconsistent both with the human instinct of self preservation and the
underlying rationale for the defence which acts as a concession to human
frailty. In addition, the Law Commission was confident in the ability of
jurors to assess adequately a defence of duress in cases of murder,
particularly in the light of the strict definition of the defence recommended
by them.
3.22
When the Law Commission revisited the issue in its final Report on a Criminal Code[287]
in 1989, it did so against the markedly different legal landscape created by
the House of Lords decision in R v Howe.[288]
Clearly influenced by that decision, it recommended that the defence should not
apply to murder or attempt to murder.[289]
3.23
In its 1993 Report on Offences against the Person, the Law
Commission identified, as already noted,[290] four main
arguments of the House of Lords in Howe in favour of
maintaining the murder exception rule.[291] In response to these, the
Commission stated:
· The
existence of a long line of authority supporting the rule is not determinative
of the issue. Parliament has not yet had an opportunity of considering
both sides of the debate;
· Innocent
life is not effectively protected by a rule of which the actor is unlikely to
be aware and is unlikely to obey. It should be for the jury to determine
whether the threat was one “which he [could not] reasonably be expected to
resist”;
· The
defence is not available to a member of a criminal or terrorist group.
Innocent tools of terrorists, however, should not be denied the defence merely
because others may claim it falsely;
· Executive
discretion is not a satisfactory solution to hard cases where a plea of duress
is raised. The defendant’s claim should be properly assessed at trial.[292]
3.24
The Law Commission noted that the concerns of those who oppose the
extension of the defence to murder could be broadly divided into two
categories, those based on principle and those based on practical concern.
Dealing first with the issue of principle, and the argument that the special
sanctity the law attached to human life cannot excuse murder, it was
acknowledged that this argument could not be lightly dismissed. However,
in the view of the Law Commission:
“it is not only futile, but also wrong, for the criminal
law to demand heroic behaviour. The attainment of a heroic standard of
behaviour will always count for great merit; but failure to achieve that
standard should not be met with punishment by the State.”[293]
3.25
The Law Commission placed emphasis on the fact that the defence acts as
an excuse and not a justification; that the actor may kill to save the lives of
third parties as well as his own; and that the defendant must also meet the
other requirements of the defence, most notably, the ‘reasonable fortitude’
requirement that the threat was one which the defendant could not reasonably
have been expected to resist.[294] In relation to the practical
objections to the extension of the defence, the Law Commission noted that these
stemmed mainly from the fact that duress is most likely to be raised in the
context of terrorist or organised crime offences and that, in such situations,
it would be easy to concoct a defence of duress which may prove extremely
difficult for the prosecution subsequently to disprove at trial. The Law
Commission felt, however, that these concerns could largely be met by its proposals
to place the burden of proof on the defendant. The reversal of the
persuasive burden would allow the Court or jury to focus on the credibility of
the defendant’s version of events, particularly the issue of voluntary exposure
to duress.[295]
3.26
The Law Commission also considered the possibility that duress could
operate as a partial defence, reducing murder to manslaughter. This was
rejected, however, on the basis that an individual who satisfied all the
requirements of the defence should not suffer the stigma of manslaughter
conviction, which is also a serious crime.
3.27
More recently the Law Commission has reconsidered the issue of applying
the defence of duress to murder. In the Consultation Paper A New
Homicide Act for England and Wales?,[296] the Law Commission proposed a new framework for homicide
offences, including “first degree” murder where the defendant intended to kill;
“second degree murder” where the defendant intended to cause serious harm,
killed as a result of reckless indifference or intended to kill but has a
partial defence; and third, manslaughter, where the defendant killed through gross
negligence, through an intentional or reckless assault or through intentional
or reckless causing of, or through the attempt to cause, some harm, or intended
to kill but has a partial defence.[297]
3.28
In relation to these proposed defences, the Law Commission provisionally
proposes that duress should be a partial defence to a charge of “first degree
murder.” The Commission notes that there are two reasons for this.
First, that this would achieve consistency with the partial defences of
provocation and diminished responsibility and second, that it reflects the fact
that the person, although having acted under duress, intentionally killed
someone, and so this is more serious that other offences committed which result
in a complete acquittal.
3.29
Regarding “second degree murder,” the Law Commission notes that there
are two options. First, duress should not be a defence to “second degree
murder” as any mitigation can be taken into account at sentencing since the
mandatory life sentence will not apply to this offence. Alternatively, duress
could lead to a complete acquittal.
3.30
In a further argument for the application of the defence of duress to
murder, at least in some cases, the Law Commission noted that there is a very
strong case that this can cause injustice among juveniles and young persons,
who are much less mature than adults and, it is argued, less able to withstand
a threat of death or serious injury. The Law Commission thus asks if
duress could be a complete defence to “first degree murder” in the case of
juveniles, or act as a partial reductive defence. This would be in
recognition of the fact that childhood immaturity reduces culpability.[298]
3.31
To summarise, the most recent recommendations of the Law Commission
involve the application of the defence of duress to murder, albeit as a partial
defence.
3.32
Section 17 of the Canadian Criminal Code[299] deals with the defence of compulsion by
threats, the Canadian equivalent of the defence of duress. The defence
has remained substantially unaltered since the first Canadian Criminal Code in
1892 and was undoubtedly influenced by the draft English Code of 1879 in
excluding many serious offences from the ambit of the defence. The list
of excluded offences is the most extensive of all the common law
jurisdictions. Indeed, the stringency of section 17 has prompted Stuart
to remark that the Canadian law on duress is “one of the most restrictive to be
found and certainly narrower than the English common law of 1892 or today.”[300]
3.33
Section 17 provides:
“A person who commits an offence under compulsion by
threats of immediate death or bodily harm from a person who is present when the
offence is committed is excused for committing the offence if the person
believes that the threats will be carried out and if the person is not a party
to a conspiracy or association whereby the person is subject to compulsion, but
this section does not apply where the offence that is committed is high
treason, murder, piracy, attempted murder, sexual assault, sexual assault with
a weapon, threats to a third party or causing bodily harm, aggravated sexual
assault, forcible abduction, hostage taking, robbery, assault with a weapon or
causing bodily harm, aggravated assault, unlawfully causing bodily harm, arson
or an offence under sections 280 to 283 (abduction and detention of young
persons).”[301]
3.34
The Code provisions apply only to actual perpetrators and not to
secondary parties to the offence. Despite dicta to the contrary
in R v Carker[302], the Supreme Court of
Canada held in R v Paquette[303] that the common law defence of duress is available to
secondary parties.[304]
It has been suggested that the decision was “borne out of the frustration as to
the narrowness of section 17… [particularly] the lengthy list of excluded
offences.”[305]
3.35
In its 1982 Working Paper on Criminal Law: the General
Part[306] the
Canadian Law Reform Commission identified the main difficulties with the law on
duress as it stood in Canada. First, the rule concerning secondary
parties differs from the law concerning principal offenders. Second,
section 17 excludes the defence from very serious crimes without articulating
any underlying principle or rationale. Third and fourth, the requirement
of immediacy arguably renders superfluous the further requirements that the
accused is not a party to a criminal conspiracy and that the duressor be present.
The third and fourth requirements have been discussed already.[307]
3.36
In order to avoid these difficulties, the Commission recommended the
following draft legislation:
“Every one is excused from criminal liability for an
offence committed by way of reasonable response to threats of serious and
immediate bodily harm to himself or those under his protection unless his
conduct manifestly endangers life or seriously violates bodily integrity.”[308]
3.37
The Canadian Law Reform Commission argued that this simplified
formulation of the defence was more comprehensive in that it applied the same
rules to secondary parties and principals. In addition, it replaced the ad hoc list of
excluded offences with a general test of danger to life or serious violation of
bodily integrity which allows the trier of fact to determine the question of
duress on the facts. For example, a robbery may not involve danger to
life or to bodily integrity in circumstances where, say, an imitation firearm
is used.
3.38
In its later Report, Recodifying Criminal Law[309],
the Commission made the following recommendation in relation to duress: “No one
is liable for committing a crime in reasonable response to threats of immediate
serious harm to himself or another person unless he himself purposely causes
the death of, or seriously harms, another person.”[310]
3.39
This clause retains the substance of the reforms proposed in the earlier
Working Paper with some slight modifications. Most significantly, the
discretion afforded to the trier of fact to decide whether a particular offence
endangers life or bodily integrity was replaced with the more familiar
requirement that the defence cannot apply to murder or offences which result in
grievous bodily harm. This proposal would result in the defence being
available to more offences than is currently the case in Canada.
3.40
In three of the six Australian states, and in the two self governing
territories, duress is regulated by statute.[311] Common law continues to apply in
the remaining three states, namely South Australia, New South Wales and
Victoria.
3.41
The defence of duress in Australia came under close scrutiny by the
Victorian Full Court in the seminal case of R v Hurley and Murray.[312] It
was noted in that case that the defence of duress is not available to murder.
3.42
While the defence does not apply to murder, two of the common law
states, New South Wales[313] and Victoria[314] allow duress to accessories to murder. In
South Australia duress is not a defence to murder in any degree.[315]
3.43
In 1899, the Griffith Code was adopted as the Criminal Code of
Queensland and was later adopted by Western Australia.[316] Section 31(4) of the Griffith
Code, which applies in Queensland and Western Australia, deals as follows with
duress. It provides:
“A person is not criminally responsible for an act
or omission when he does or omits to do the act in order to save himself from
immediate death or grievous bodily harm threatened to be inflicted upon him by
some person actually present and in a position to execute the threats, and
believing himself to be unable otherwise to escape the carrying of the threats into
execution.”[317]
3.44
Under the Griffith Code, a number of serious offences are excluded from
the scope of duress. These are treason, murder, piracy, and offences of
which grievous bodily harm or an intention to cause grievous bodily harm is an
element.
3.45
The Griffith Code has also influenced the other criminal codes in
Australia. The sections of the Tasmanian Code, for example, are not
dissimilar although it will be noted that the excluded offences under the
Tasmanian Code are more extensive than the Griffith Code:
“…compulsion by threats of immediate death or
grievous bodily harm, from a person actually present at the commission of the
offence, shall be an excuse for the commission, by a person subject to such
threats, and who believes that such threats will be executed, and who is not a
party to such association or conspiracy the being a party to which rendered him
subject to compulsion, of any offence other than treason, murder, piracy,
offences deemed to be piracy, attempting to murder, rape, forcible abduction,
aggravated armed robbery, armed robbery, robbery, causing grievous bodily harm,
and arson.”[318]
3.46
In the Northern Territory the defence is not available to those charged
with murder, manslaughter, or a crime of which grievous bodily harm or an
intention to cause such harm is an element, or to those who have exposed
themselves to the risk of duress.[319] The harshness of this provision
is mitigated somewhat by section 41 of the Code which allows for a partial
defence of coercion in relation to murder. If the requirements of the
defence are satisfied, then the charge will be reduced from murder to
manslaughter.[320]
3.47
The provisions of the Australian Capital Territory and Commonwealth
Codes which deal with duress are drafted in virtually identical terms, and do
not contain any reference to a limitation in the scope of the defence:
“… (2) A person carries out conduct under duress if
and only if he or she reasonably believes that:
(a) a threat has been made that will be carried out
unless an offence is committed; and
(b) there is no reasonable way that the threat can
be rendered ineffective; and
(c) the conduct is a reasonable response to the
threat.
(3)
This section does not apply if the threat is made by or on behalf of a person
with whom the person under duress is voluntarily associating for the purpose of
carrying out conduct of the kind actually carried out.”[321]
3.48
The South Australia Criminal Law and Penal Methods Committee in a 1977 Report
on the Substantive Criminal Law recommended that duress should be a full
defence to murder if the accused is deprived of any power to resist what is
demanded of him.[322]
If the accused’s choice of action was impaired substantially,
then he should be guilty of manslaughter. The recommendations were as
follows:
“[W]here the defendant is by reason of duress
deprived of any power to resist compliance with what is demanded of him, and
kills another in consequence, he should be guilty of no criminal offence…
[W]here by reason of duress the defendant’s power of choice of action is
substantially impaired, and he kills another in consequence, he should be
guilty of manslaughter.” [323]
3.49
The Law Reform Commission of Victoria, in a Working Paper on Duress, Necessity and
Coercion,[324]
suggested that the recommendations of the English Law Commission Report of 1977
should form the basis of any proposed legislative changes.[325]
3.50
The definition of duress in its subsequent Report incorporated two
defences, the traditional defence of duress as well as a defence termed
“excusatory necessity” (that is, duress of circumstances).[326] The Commission recommended that
the defence be available to a person who commits an offence under compulsion
(whether human or of circumstances), with the following conditions:
· In
the case of murder which was intentional or where death was expected, belief
need not be reasonable but the harm threatened must have been death or serious
personal injury to the actor, or someone closely connected with him;
· In
all other murder cases, or cases of indictable injuries to the person, the harm
threatened is extended to include torture, rape, buggery or unlawful
imprisonment to the same persons as above.
3.51
It was noted in the report that it is left to the jury to decide on
moral culpability, if there is none then they must acquit, if there is some
degree, but not enough to satisfy a murder charge, then the verdict should be
manslaughter. [327]
3.52
The Report discussed in detail the possibility of allowing duress as a
defence to murder, and recommended that it should be available, regardless of
the extent of participation by the defendant. Having considered the law
of DPP for Northern
Ireland v Lynch[328] and
R v Abbott[329] the
Commission concluded that the illogical and unjust distinction between those
accused of murder in the second degree and principals in the first degree
should be removed, but that the defence should only be available if the harm
threatened is death or serious personal injury.[330] In other cases
the ambit of harm threatened was widened to allow for torture, rape, buggery or
unlawful imprisonment.[331]
The Report called for a greater degree of flexibility in this area of the law.[332]
3.53
The Law Reform Commission of Victoria considered the issue of duress
again in its 1991 Report on Homicide in which it advocated the
application of the defence of duress to murder.[333]
3.54
More recently, the Law Reform Commission of Victoria considered the area
in the 2004 Final Report on Defences to Homicide.[334] Having considered the arguments
for allowing duress as a defence to murder, including the arguments as laid out
in the 1980 and 1991 Reports, the Commission recommended the application of the
defences of duress and extraordinary emergency to murder and attempted murder.[335]
3.55
Like the Canadian law on duress, the law in New Zealand has also been
informed by the draft English Code of 1879 and it therefore bears a striking
similarity to the Canadian Code. The law in this area is governed by
section 24 of the Crimes
Act 1961. The section re-enacts provisions found in the 1893 and
1908 Codes which were derived from the Draft Code of 1879. The section
reads:
“(1) Subject to the provisions of this section, a
person who commits an offence under compulsion by threats of immediate death or
grievous bodily harm from a person who is present when the offence is committed
is protected from criminal responsibility if he believes that the threats will
be carried out and if he is not a party to any association or conspiracy
whereby he is subject to compulsion.
(2) Nothing in subsection (1) of this section shall
apply where the offence committed is [any of the following offences: treason,
communicating secrets, sabotage, piracy, piratical acts, murder, attempt to
murder, wounding with intent, injuring with intent to cause grievous bodily
harm, abduction, kidnapping, robbery, aggravated robbery, arson].”[336]
3.56
Like Canada, New Zealand has an extensive list of offences which are
excluded from the defence. The section is silent as to whether the list
of excluded offences applies to secondary parties, which thereby left open the
possibility that the view of the Canadian Supreme Court in Paquette[337] could
also be followed in New Zealand. The matter was put beyond doubt in R
v Witika[338] where
the Court of Appeal, relying on R v Howe,[339] held
that there was no justification for the defences of duress or compulsion to be
different for secondary parties for the defence. The Court held that the
correct construction of section 24 of the Code was that it includes both types
of offender because where a distinction is drawn in other sections of the Code
the expression “actually commits” is used.
3.57
The common law in the USA permits duress as a defence to a charge of any
crime except murder. The general rule, however, is that the doing of a
prohibited act is not a crime if reasonably believed to be necessary to save
the actor from imminent death or great bodily injury. The defence has
been applied in prosecutions for reckless driving, malicious mischief, larceny,
embezzlement, receiving stolen goods and even in respect of more serious
offences such as burglary, robbery, kidnapping and arson.[340]
3.58
Many of the restrictions placed on the operation of the defence at
common law, however, are not to be found in the provisions of the American Law
Institute’s Model Penal Code which has been adopted
by a majority of the American states. The provisions on duress are to be
found in section 2.09 of Article 2 which deals with General Principles of
Criminal Liability:
“(1) It is an affirmative defense that the actor
engaged in the conduct charged to constitute the offense because he was coerced
to do so by the use of, or a threat to use, unlawful force against his person
or the person of another, which a person of reasonable firmness in his
situation would have been unable to resist.
(2) The defense provided by this Section is
unavailable if the actor recklessly placed himself in a situation in which it
was probable that he would be subjected to duress. The defense is also
unavailable if he was negligent in placing himself in such a situation,
whenever negligence suffices to establish culpability for the offense charged.”[341]
3.59
The Model Penal Code adopts a very general formula thus conferring a
fairly broad discretion on the court or jury to decide each case according to
the moral culpability of the accused. It specifically provides that the
threats can be made against anyone and it is notable that the mere infliction
of force or a threat to apply force will supply a defence. Significantly,
no limitation as to murder is included in the section. However, a
majority of US states that have decided on the issue have declined to allow
duress as a defence to murder.[342]
3.60
South African law does not make the traditional distinction between
situations where an accused’s choice is constrained by human agents (duress or
compulsion) or by virtue of the surrounding circumstances (necessity).
Instead, the law favours a broad defence of necessity with one set of
principles applicable in both instances.[343] This latter form of necessity as
it exists in South African law will be discussed in more detail later in this
Paper.[344]
3.61
In relation to the applicability of the defence to murder, early South
African cases, such as R v Werner,[345] followed
the approach of the English courts in holding that it is never justified to
take the life of another to save one’s own. The leading case on the
subject, however, is now S v Goliath[346] which
allows the defence on a charge of murder.
3.62
The facts of S v Goliath were that
the two accused came across their victim while out walking one night.
They asked him for money and upon being told he had none, the principal
offender stabbed the deceased in the chest while his accessory bound the
deceased’s arms behind his back. The accessory claimed that he did so
under threats from the principal that he would stab him to death. At
their subsequent trial for murder, the principal was found guilty of murder and
was sentenced to death, while the accessory was acquitted on the ground that he
acted under the principal’s compulsion. On an appeal by the prosecution
on a point of law, Rumpff JA, delivering the leading judgment, held that
compulsion or duress can constitute a complete defence to a charge of murder if
the pressure brought to bear on an accused was so strong that no reasonable
person in the circumstances of the accused could be expected to have resisted
it.[347]
The Court dismissed dicta
to the contrary in R v Werner as being obiter and observed
that the murder exception rule was an historical hangover from old English
decisions and writers who were influenced by the ethical considerations of
their time. He also noted that the correctness of this position had
subsequently been doubted by modern writers on English and American law and
that this was no longer the law in many continental countries. Rumpff JA
was therefore fortified in arriving at the conclusion that heroism should not
be expected of ordinary individuals:
“It is generally accepted…that for the ordinary person
in general his life is more valuable than that of another. Only they who
possess the quality of heroism will intentionally offer their lives for
another. Should the criminal law then state that compulsion could never
be a defence to a charge of murder, it would demand that a person who killed
another under duress, whatever the circumstances, would have to comply with a
higher standard than that demanded of the average person. I do not think
that such an exception to the general rule which applies in criminal law is
justified.”[348]
3.63
It would be a misinterpretation of Goliath to state that
South African courts lightly accept compulsion as a defence to murder. As
observed by Rumpff JA, the facts of the case will be carefully scrutinised and
of course the accused will have to satisfy the reasonable person test.
3.64
Before leaving South African law, it should be noted that both the
majority and minority in Goliath also expressed
support for a partial defence of compulsion where the reasonable person would
not have committed the crime. This would allow a court or jury to return
a verdict of culpable homicide and not murder. However, in S v Bailey[349] this rule was rejected as contrary to
principle and logic, because if the accused intended to kill he or she must be
guilty of murder if the other elements of the crime are present.
3.65
To summarise, the denial of the defence of duress in cases of murder is
reflected in the common law and statutory codes of many jurisdictions.
The English Law Commission has consistently recommended that it be allowed as a
full defence, and the logic of the Commission’s argument was recently
described in the House of Lords as “irresistible.”[350]
3.66
While many of the older academic works on the subject tend not to be in
favour of extending duress to murder, it has been suggested that these writers
should not be compelling in a modern context.[351] Thus, the minority judges in R v Abbott stated that
“they have to be read with circumspection in these days, for the criminal
courts have long accepted duress as an available defence to a large number of
crimes from which those same writers withheld it.”[352]
3.67
More modern academic works have tended to argue for, at the very least,
a reconsideration of the denial of the defence to murder. These have
noted that the denial of the defence is based on past ethical standards and
that there is a discernible trend towards moving from the strict common law
position that the defence is unavailable in murder cases.[353] Stuart notes also that most
English commentators suggest that no offence, including murder, should be
automatically excluded from the scope of the defence.[354]
3.68
The Commission now turns to discuss the various issues that arise in
this respect.
3.69
It has been suggested that close examination of the weight of authority
against the availability of the defence reveals mainly reiteration of Hale’s
assertion in this regard.[355]
It is of course the case that Hale’s writings were based on the ethical
standards of the time. In that respect, it may be open to question whether
today’s society is likely to be guided by such standards, or would be more
willing to consider arguments based on threats to personal autonomy.
3.70
There is a long line of authority to the effect that where a person is
forced to choose between sacrificing his or her own life and taking that of
another, the correct moral choice is to sacrifice their own life.[356]
This is based on the sanctity of life. However it has been noted that perhaps
the criminal law should no longer expect heroism.[357] It has been suggested that apart from a
few exceptional cases, there is no duty in the criminal law to be a hero.[358]
3.71
If an act can be excused this means that the act was undoubtedly a
crime, but the law recognises that the actor was placed in very difficult
circumstances and may have been coerced into committing the crime.
Allowing the defence to be used in murder cases allows the criminal law to
deplore the act but excuse the actor. It is by no means justifying the
act.
3.72
If the law recognises, on the basis of human frailty, that the defence
of provocation should be available to a person who is provoked to kill, there
is an argument that equally the law should make provisions for the human
weakness that is at play when a person is coerced to kill.
3.73
Duress, like self defence, is preventative, that is, the defendant
acts to avert harm, while the former merely operates retrospectively.[359]
3.74
It has been suggested that denial of the plea of duress in murder cases
may have a deterrent effect on a person under duress.[360] Nonetheless, it can also be
argued that the imposition of such a standard will not necessarily act as an
effective deterrent. It may be more likely that a person faced with such
difficult circumstances that they find themselves under duress to commit a murder
is unlikely to consider the possibility that they are breaking the criminal law
and the consequences thereof. In fact, it has been suggested that the
instinct of self preservation in the face of an immediate threat will nearly
always take precedence over the threat of legal punishment at some future date.[361]
3.75
One of the main arguments against the extension of the defence to murder
is that the law may be seen to be countenancing, even incentivising,
murder. It then appears that the sanctity of life is being ignored by the
courts in favour of compassion to someone who, although coerced into doing it,
has murdered someone.
3.76
Another important argument in this respect is that the State should
encourage high standards of human behaviour by withholding the defence of
duress in situations where individuals are compelled to commit murder. It
was noted in R v Howe[362] that one of the objectives of the criminal law
is to “set a standard which ordinary men and women are expected to observe” and
clearly the law cannot excuse the killing of an innocent person. This is
true yet, as noted above, to allow duress as a defence to murder is not to
justify the act, that is, to say that the act was the right thing to do in the
circumstances, but to excuse the actor, by recognising that he or she acted
under constrained choice, while still deploring the act.
3.77
It can be argued that the defence of duress is particularly susceptible
to fabrication. As a result, it has been suggested that it would be
unwise to offer what may be perceived to be an easy defence to a serious
crime. As noted in the House of Lords in R v Howe, “the defence of
duress is so easy to raise and may be so difficult for the prosecution to
disprove beyond reasonable doubt, the facts of necessity being as a rule known
only to the defendant himself.”[363]
3.78
It was suggested by Lord Simon in DPP for Northern Ireland v Lynch,[364]
as well as being noted in R v Howe,[365] that the leader of a gang, through
coercion, could confer immunity on his or her followers, thereby leading to
many deaths of innocent victims.
3.79
However this “charter for terrorism” argument supposes that, once
raised, the defence will invariably succeed. The current objective
elements in the duress defence result in its denial where the defendant’s
behaviour has been unreasonable. Further, the prior fault rule would deny
the defence to terrorists or members of criminal gangs.[366]
3.80
There have been suggestions that an appropriate way of dealing with
these difficult cases is to leave them to prosecutorial discretion.[367]
However this is countered by the argument that it may be seen as an evasion of
the issue to delegate difficult cases to the public prosecutor. Some
commentators feel that the issue should be faced and that the validity of the
defence in individual cases is better judged at trial than by government
officials.[368]
The Canadian Law Reform Commission noted in the 1982 Working Paper on
Criminal Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences[369]
that this approach would lead to a divergence of law in code and law in
practice and would also lead to a lack of jurisprudence in the area.
3.81
The Commission considers that it is equally arguable that prosecutorial
discretion combined with other factors such as the use of the defence to reduce
murder to manslaughter and discretion in sentencing may be a more appropriate
way to deal with individual cases as it would allow a degree of flexibility for
the more difficult cases.
3.82
It is also noteworthy that although the Law Commission of England and
Wales have consistently called for changes in this area of the law, the UK
Parliament has not acted on these recommendations. In the Commission’s
view this shows a consistent lack of legislative will to extend the
defence.
3.83
If it is to be recommended that duress should not provide a complete
defence to murder, it is nevertheless important to consider whether it should
act as a partial defence, reducing the plea to manslaughter.
3.84
The Court of Appeal in R v Howe noted that if duress is to act as
a defence to murder at all, it should only reduce the offence from murder to
manslaughter.[370]
It was suggested in that case that the defence of duress could have developed
more logically as mitigation, as suggested by Stephen.[371]
3.85
It has been noted that in the recent decision in R v Hasan, Lord
Bingham suggested that the strictness of the parameters of the defence can be
supported when one bears in mind that judges can have regard to duress at the
sentencing stage, even if the strict requirements of duress have not been
satisfied.[372]
Thus, it has been suggested that the focus towards the conceptual underpinnings
of the defence is shifting back to the approach advocated by Lord Simon in his
dissenting judgment in DPP
for Northern Ireland v Lynch, where he expressed the view that duress
should go to mitigation, but not liability.[373]
3.86
Many of the arguments put forward in relation to duress being used as a
full defence also apply to the suggestion that it should be used as a partial
defence. However the arguments for a partial defence allow for a balance
between recognising the sanctity of life and recognising the difficult
situation that those who fall under duress are placed in.
3.87
The English Law Commission recently considered the issue of allowing
duress as a partial defence to “first degree murder” in its proposed new
homicide framework.[374]
The Law Commission recommended that the defence of duress should act as a
partial defence giving the following reasoning. First, that by allowing
duress to act as a partial defence, consistency would be achieved with the
partial defences of provocation and diminished responsibility and second, that
it would reflect the fact that the person, although having acted under duress,
intentionally killed someone, and so this is more serious than other offences
committed which result in a complete acquittal.
3.88
On a policy basis, it seems appropriate that if the defence is not to
apply as a full defence to murder, some provision should be made for those who
kill while under serious threats, to reflect the fact that they acted under
duress due to their being “caught in a maelstrom of circumstances.”[375]
3.89
Allowing the defence of duress to act as a partial defence to murder
would have the advantage of flexibility (the mandatory penalty of life
imprisonment is avoided) so that duress could be taken into account in
sentencing. The moral culpability of the accused, as determined by the
particular circumstances of the case, could then be reflected in the sentence.
The defendant would still remain guilty but the court could take into account
that he or she was coerced into committing the crime.
3.90
It is arguable that such flexibility is particularly important in cases
where people have killed under duress. The defendant can be seen as
somewhat less blameworthy, due to the fact that they have acted as a result of
threats.
3.91
The English Law Commission recently provisionally proposed the
application of duress as a partial defence to “first degree murder”.[376]
It is noted in the Consultation Paper that the main justification for allowing
the defence to murder is to “obviate the effect of a mandatory life sentence.”[377]
3.92
If the defence is allowed to act as a partial defence to murder, the
courts will have the opportunity to take into account the sanctity of life
while still showing compassion to the accused. Ashworth points out that a
qualified defence allows the law to recognise the sanctity of human life while
showing compassion.[378]
3.93
A person who acts under duress has intentionally taken an innocent life,
but it could be argued that they cannot be regarded as fully blameworthy as
their will was impaired. Allowing them to rely on the defence of duress
ensures that this lower level of blameworthiness is recognised by the courts.
3.94
Although the Court of Appeal in R v Howe[379] suggested that if duress is to act as a defence in
murder it should only be as mitigation, Lord Griffiths, citing Lord Morris’ in DPP for Northern Ireland v
Lynch,[380] stated
that it is too late now to adopt that view. Lord Griffiths added
that this compromise solution should not be accepted saying that “[w]here the
defence of duress is available it is a complete excuse.”[381]
He went on to note that English law has rejected the use of duress as
mitigation and thus it would be yet another anomaly in the law of duress to
allow it as mitigation for murder alone. Although there were various
views in relation to the logic of allowing duress as a defence to murder, there
was a general agreement that such change, if it were to be introduced, should
be effected by Parliament.
3.95
This argument can be countered by the acknowledgement that murder, as it
involves the taking of another human life, may be treated differently to other
offences. Thus, it follows that defences to murder may be different to
defences to other offences. The argument that murder may be treated
differently is borne out by the fact that provocation only applies in the
context of reducing murder to manslaughter.[382]
3.96
As noted above, it is difficult to find a logical reason to apply duress
as a partial defence to murder. One rationale apparent is to treat duress
in murder as analogous to provocation. Duress is analogous to
provocation, which is a partial defence to murder, in so far as it is excusatory
in nature and arguably should operate to like effect. The law excuses the
offender on the basis of the common human emotions of anger in provocation and
fear in duress.[383]
However the analogy is weakened by the fact that provocation is only a partial
defence to murder whereas duress is a complete defence to all crimes except murder.[384] As already noted, this can be
rationalised by the fact that murder may be treated differently to other
offences.
3.97
The Law Commission of England and Wales considered the possibility of
allowing duress to reduce murder to manslaughter, and rejected the suggestion
on the basis that an individual who satisfies all the requirements of the
duress defence should not be subject to the stigma of a conviction for
manslaughter, which is still a serious crime.[385]
3.98
Nonetheless, it is essential that the criminal law views the killing as
a crime, because not to do so would be to ignore the sanctity of life, and
allow someone who has taken a human life to go unpunished. Extending
duress to murder, as a partial defence, can ensure that the acts of the
defendant are seen as a crime, but allow the courts to excuse the person who
submitted to the threats and carried out the crime.
3.99
The denial of the defence of duress in cases of murder is reflected in
the law and Codes of many common law jurisdictions. As discussed above,
the English Law Commission has consistently recommended that it be allowed as a
full defence,[386]
and the logic of the Commission’s argument was recently described in the House
of Lords as “irresistible”.[387]
The Victorian Law Reform Commission also recently recommended that duress
should be available as a defence to murder and manslaughter in Victoria,[388]
while it is a defence to murder under the Commonwealth and ACT Criminal Codes.[389]
3.100
The Commission acknowledges the fact that the issue of the scope of the
defence of duress is a difficult and complex issue. It is also noted that
that it is very seldom that cases arise that fit the mould of ‘the perfect
duress case’. There seems to be an automatic instinctive reaction in
society which shows a reluctance to extend the defence to murder, as reflected
by the reluctance of the legislature to extend the defence, but there is some
possibility of the creation of circumstances under which duress can be used as
a partial defence in cases of murder. For the reasons outlined above,
including flexibility and discretion in sentencing, it seems that allowing the
defence of duress to be available to those who commit murder, in order to
reduce murder to manslaughter, is a viable option. This by no means will
ensure that all of those who plead duress to murder will have their plea
accepted and their charge reduced to manslaughter; it merely means that the
option is there in those cases where such a reduction and sentencing discretion
is appropriate. On balance, the Commission has provisionally concluded
that the defence of duress should apply to all crimes excluding murder and
attempted murder, but that it should apply as a partial defence to those
crimes, reducing the charge of murder to that of manslaughter.
3.101
The Commission acknowledges that, as already discussed,[390]
this conclusion is predicated on an analysis whose focus is on the element of
constrained choice operating in duress cases. On this analysis the
defendant is entitled to be excused, or partially excused, because it would be
unfair to hold him accountable for his actions by reason of the element of
moral compulsion. If, on the other hand, the focus is shifted to the
choice of evils confronting the defendant, an arguable case can be made that an
accused who chooses the lesser of two evils is entitled to a complete
acquittal. On this view, the argument is that the accused’s actions,
though regrettable, are nevertheless justifiable; by effecting a net saving of
human life he has done the right thing in the circumstances. Accordingly,
the argument from justification points to a full, rather than partial, defence
to murder in cases of this kind, and, on the principle of fair and proper
labelling, to an acquittal on the grounds of lesser evils rather than duress.
While expressing an initial preference for the excusatory analysis, the
Commission acknowledges that a coherent case can be made for the justificatory
approach and would welcome views on this matter.
3.102
The Commission provisionally recommends that the defence of duress
should apply to all offences excluding murder and attempted murder.
Moreover, while acknowledging that the plea might be made available as a
partial defence to those offences, the Commission accepts that a coherent case
can also be made for treating duress as a complete defence where
the accused’s actions can be justified on the grounds of lesser evils, and
invites submissions on this matter.
4.01
In this Chapter, the Commission considers the defence of necessity and
its connection with duress. The Commission also discusses the more recent
development in English law of the defence of duress of circumstances.[391]
4.02
There is a significant overlap between the defences of necessity and
duress in that they both involve an element of constrained choice. Indeed
necessity is sometimes referred to as duress per necessitatum (duress by
necessity or coercion). They can be distinguished because duress involves
the will being overborne by threats while necessity involves the will being
overborne by external circumstances.
4.03
It is generally accepted that necessity is a recognised defence in Irish
law, although its application is narrowly circumscribed, and for that reason
its status as a general defence can be questioned. But there are clear
examples where a person is, in effect, by virtue of the extraordinarily
constrained circumstances in which they find themselves, permitted to break the
letter of the criminal law in order to prevent another evil to them or another
person, or, sometimes, to other property.[392]
4.04
A common law example of necessity is where a doctor operates on an
unconscious person who cannot give consent to the operation, in order to save
the person’s life.[393] Without the
consent of the patient, the operation amounts to an assault, but the necessity
of the situation provides a defence for the doctor. A statutory example
is section 6 of the Criminal Damage Act 1991[394] which
states that it is a defence to a charge of criminal damage to property that the
intentional damage was done to avoid injury to a person or to save other
property and where this damage was reasonable in the circumstances.
Emergency rescue teams who cut through a car to save a person trapped in the
car or fire officers who deliberately knock a building to prevent a fire
spreading to other buildings come within section 6 of the 1991 Act.
4.05
The common law origins of necessity as a defence date back to the 16th
Century decision in Reniger v Fogossa.[395]
In a celebrated argument, it was noted that:
“in every law there are some things which when they
happen a man may break the words of the law, and yet not break the law itself;
and such things are exempted out of the penalty of the law…where the words of
them are broken to avoid greater inconveniences, or through necessity, or by
compulsion… ”[396]
Williams points to various
sources justifying necessity as a defence and “somewhat confidently” asserts
the existence of the defence in English law.[397]
4.06
In recent years the defence has been applied by English courts, most
often in a medical context. This includes the use of necessity to justify
the sterilisation of a mentally incapacitated woman,[398] and the detention of a person suffering
from a mental disorder.[399]
In Re F,[400] Lord
Goff noted that “there exists in the common law a principle of necessity which
may justify action which would otherwise be unlawful” and in R v Bournewood
Community and Mental Health NHS Trust[401] he
noted that “the concept of necessity has its role to play …in our criminal law”
and went on to note that it is “a concept of great importance.”
4.07
The doctrine of necessity was used in the Bournewood Trust case
as the legal basis for the detention of a person suffering from mental
disorder. This decision was subsequently overruled in the European Court
of Human Rights because using necessity as a standard meant that there were no
procedural safeguards to protect against an arbitrary deprivation of liberty.[402]
4.08
In R v Shayler[403]
the Court of Appeal stated, obiter, that the defence of necessity
existed almost entirely in the excusatory defence of “duress of
circumstances”. This has been criticised on the basis that the Court
denied the existence of the defence of necessity without very compelling
reasoning and that it “merely draws together what are really no more than a few
incautious remarks in other sources” before denying the distinction between
excusatory and justificatory forms of necessity.[404] Indeed, as Lord Bingham noted in
the House of Lords, on appeal, it was a little unfortunate that the Court of
Appeal had entered this “vexed and uncertain territory”, as the defendant had
not raised the issue of necessity or duress.[405]
4.09
In R v Quayle ,[406] the Court of Appeal outlined some
requirements that a defendant must satisfy in order to plead the defence of
necessity. Although this case is a medical case also, it appeared to
accept a general defence of necessity.
4.10
In any treatment on the defence of necessity in English law, it is
appropriate to deal with the leading case R v Dudley and Stephens.[407]
While the case primarily looks at the scope of the defence and its application
to homicide, its influence in English law has been far-reaching.
4.11
In R v Dudley
and Stephens, the Queen’s Bench Division vigorously denied the
existence of any doctrine of necessity as a defence to murder. The facts
of this case are well-known. The two defendants, a 17 year old cabin boy
and another man got into an open lifeboat after their ship, the Mignonette,
had sunk. They had been in the boat for 18 days, their food and water
supplies having run out, when Dudley proposed to Stephens that one of them
should be killed and eaten by the survivors. It was decided that the
cabin boy would be killed, and he was at that stage very weak. They did so and
4 days later they were rescued. When they arrived in England they were
charged with murder. The jury found, as a matter of fact, that the men
would probably have died within the four days had they not fed on the boy’s
body; that the boy would probably have died before them and that, at the time
of the killing, there was no appreciable chance of survival by any other
means. On these facts, the court, in a judgment delivered by Lord
Coleridge, convicted the defendants and sentenced them to death. However,
this sentence was later commuted to six months imprisonment.[408]
4.12
Lord Coleridge appeared to base his judgment on two grounds. The
first was morality; the judgment appears to suggest that the only morally correct
course of action in such circumstances is to sacrifice oneself for
others. In this regard, Lord Coleridge stated that “[w]e are often
compelled to set up standards we cannot reach ourselves, and to lay down rules
we could not ourselves satisfy.” His second reason for denying the
defence was “the difficulty of measuring necessity and selecting the victim…By
what measure is the comparative value of lives to be measured?”
4.13
However, as noted by Williams “to hinge guilt on [choosing the boy as
the victim] would indicate that lots should have been drawn”[409] and, as the Court had already
disapproved, obiter,
of a decision in the United States case of US v Holmes[410] that
the drawing of lots in similar circumstances to those in Dudley and Stephens would
afford an accused a defence, this sheds little light on the Court’s
reasoning. Significantly, the judgment also fails to lay down any
alternative rules of action in the circumstances which would allow some lives
to be saved. In US
v Holmes, the defendant, a member of the crew of the wrecked ship the William Brown, was
cast adrift in an over-crowded boat. In an attempt to prevent the boat
from sinking, Holmes, under orders from the first mate, assisted in throwing 16
men overboard. The grand jury declined to indict him for murder and,
charged with manslaughter, he sought to rely on a defence of necessity. Baldwin
CJ in his direction to the jury accepted the existence of a defence of
necessity justifying the taking of another’s life if the person was in
circumstances of imperious necessity, but noted that passengers should be
chosen above seamen, with enough seamen left to man the boat. Those
passengers whom necessity requires to be cast overboard should be chosen by
lot.
4.14
Lord Coleridge in Dudley and Stephens
dismissed Holmes as
unlikely to be an “authority satisfactory to a court in this country”. No
alternative solution to this problem was offered by him and it appears that the
intention would be that, in the absence of a self-sacrificing volunteer, it
would be the duty of all to die. Lord Coleridge noted that “[t]o preserve
one’s life is generally speaking, a duty, but it may be the plainest and the
highest duty to sacrifice it.”[411] He went on to reject the defence
of necessity as unworkable and dangerous in practice. It has been
suggested that this rejection of the principle was obiter as there was no
necessity on the facts.[412]
4.15
Lord Coleridge’s dismissal of Holmes and the lottery
principle does not seem to be part of the ratio decidendi, given
that the boy in Dudley
and Stephens was not fairly chosen. Also, it should be noted that
Lord Coleridge’s refusal to accept the necessity plea was as a result of his
refusal to accept Bacon’s maxim that self preservation was a defence for the
deliberate taking of innocent life. The defendant who acts in pursuit of
a common agreement to secure a net saving of human life in circumstances where everyone
will perish if he does nothing is not an example of the selfish individual Lord
Coleridge had in mind. Therefore the principle does not seem to apply
where there is no need to select a victim, and there is also a net saving of
human life. It follows then that Dudley and Stephens
could be distinguished if the person sacrificed has innocently imperilled the
lives of others. This is used as an argument for the defence of necessity
in certain cases where the victim, by creating the peril, has selected himself,
for example, as in the case of the man on the ladder in the Zeebrugge disaster.[413]
4.16
Some critics suggest that the R v Dudley and Stephens judgment
was unsatisfactory. The grounds of the decision, that necessity “might be
made the legal cloak for unbridled passion and atrocious crime” have been
described as “mere rhetoric”[414]
and “scarcely realistic”.[415]
4.17
One commentator suggests that R v Dudley and Stephens
in fact casts more shadow than light on the subject of necessity, asserting
that the case does not prove that necessity exists, but that another reason
must be sought for stating that it does not.[416] It has also been suggested that
even in light of the more recent House of Lords approval of R v Dudley and Stephens
in R v Howe[417] it
may be “premature to conclude that necessity can never be a defence to murder.”[418]
4.18
The decision in R v Dudley and Stephens was approved by the House
of Lords in R v Howe[419]
in support of their decision that the defence of duress did not apply to a
conspiracy to murder charge. Prior to Howe, there was some
uncertainty as to whether the defence was open to some accessories to
murder. In R v Abbott[420]
a majority of the Privy Council had confirmed that the defence of duress would
not be allowed in the case of first-degree murder. However, in DPP for Northern Ireland v
Lynch[421] the
majority of the House of Lords allowed the defence of duress to an alleged
principal in the second degree to murder. Lynch was threatened by
terrorists and forced to drive them to a place where a shooting was carried
out. This finding, however, had been criticised on the basis that a
principal in the second degree on a murder charge, may be just, if not more,
morally culpable than the actual perpetrator. Accordingly, when the
matter came up for re-consideration in R v Howe the Lords
took the opportunity to restore the law to its pre-Lynch position.
Lord Hailsham was strongly influenced by the decision in R v Dudley and Stephens, describing the distinction
between duress and necessity as being one without a difference. He
stated: “I do not believe that as a ‘concession to human frailty’ […those who
succumb to the temptation of taking an innocent life rather than their own]
should be exempt from liability to criminal sanctions.”[422]
4.19
Lord Hailsham was thus dissociating himself from the view expressed by
the South African Supreme Court in S v Goliath[423],
and approved in R v Abbott[424]
that “it is generally accepted… that for the ordinary person in general his
life is more valuable than that of another.”[425] In Goliath, Rumpff JA had
also noted “I do not think that such an exception to the general rule which
applies in criminal law is justified.”[426]
4.20
In R v Howe
Lord Hailsham concluded that:
“in general I must say that I do not at all accept
in relation to the defence of duress it is either good morals, good policy or
good law to suggest, as did the majority in Lynch’s case and the
minority in R v Abbott that the ordinary man of reasonable fortitude is
not to be supposed to be capable of heroism if he is asked to take an innocent
life rather than sacrifice his own.”[427]
4.21
R v Howe
appears to be authority that the defence of necessity would be not available in
cases of murder. However, the conjoined twins case Re A (Children)[428]
has been said to show an increased willingness of English law to accept the
defence of necessity in the case of murder.
4.22
The decision in Re A (Children) concerned J and M, conjoined
twins, of whom J was capable of an independent existence, but an operation to
separate the twins would have caused the death of M. Without any operation,
both would die. The twins’ parents refused to consent to the operation,
and so the hospital applied for a declaration that performing the operation
would be lawful. The judge concluded that the operation would be
lawful. While each of the judges appeared to have varying rationales for
the decision, Brooke LJ referred considerably to the doctrine of
necessity. He held that both Dudley and Stephens[429]
and R v Howe,[430]
in which necessity and duress respectively were denied as a defence to murder,
were distinguishable on policy reasons. He went on to reject the
assumptions of some critics that the recognition of the defence of necessity in
such a case would give rise to people being all too ready to avail themselves
of exceptions to the law which they might suppose to apply to their cases (at
the risk of other people’s lives). He emphasised the rare circumstances
of the case, thereby reducing the possibility of the necessity defence being
relied upon in subsequent murder cases.
4.23
In his judgment, Brooke LJ, having discussed R v Dudley and Stephens
in detail, went on to describe some classic examples of the necessity
doctrine. These included events during the sinking of the ferry The
Herald of Free Enterprise near Zeebrugge where a man on the sinking
ferry was pushed to his death from a rope ladder in order to allow several
others to save themselves.[431] Brooke LJ noted academic
commentary which suggested that if such a case were to come to court now, it
would not be too difficult for a judge to distinguish Dudley and Stephens.
He gave two reasons for this belief. The first was that there was no
question of choosing who had to die (the problem which Lord Coleridge had found
unanswerable in R v
Dudley and Stephens[432])
because the unfortunate young man on the ladder had chosen himself by his
immobility there. The second was that unlike the cabin boy on the Mignonette,
the young man, although in no way at fault, was preventing others from going
where they had a right - and a most urgent need - to go, and was thereby
unwittingly imperilling their lives.
4.24
The issue of the difficulty of choosing a victim was also discussed by
Brooke LJ in Re A (Children).[433] It was noted that to allow a
victim to be chosen is to regard the victim’s rights as less worthy than the
rights of the person protected by the action taken, but that it is surely
necessary to make some sacrifice, and a fair procedure for resolving the
problem must be found. Brooke LJ held that the 3 requirements for the
application of the doctrine of necessity, as laid down by Sir James Stephen,
were satisfied. These were that the act is needed to avoid inevitable and
irreparable evil; that no more should be done than is reasonably necessary for
the purpose to be achieved; and that the evil inflicted must not be
disproportionate to the evil avoided, were satisfied.
4.25
While Re A (Children) appears to be an acceptance of the doctrine
of necessity as a defence to murder, it must be noted that the judgment itself
relied heavily on the specific facts of the case, thereby precluding the
general assertion that the defence can be available in homicide cases.
4.26
Not only has the decision in R v Dudley and Stephens affected
homicide cases, but all subsequent decisions in the area. The
narrow limits that have been placed on the defence of necessity, coupled with
cases which have denied the existence of the defence has led to a situation in
which the scope, application and very existence of the defence is unclear.
As noted above, the defence has been applied more recently, albeit in the
context of medical law, in Re A (Children)[434]
and R v Quayle.
4.27
In R v Quayle,[435] a number of defendants, all of whom had
been separately charged and tried in relation to the possession and use, and in
some cases, supply of cannabis had pleaded the defence of necessity at
trial. This was on the basis that the defendants needed to use the
cannabis for medicinal purposes. In 3 of the 5 cases the defence had not
been left to the jury, and in one of those cases that it had been allowed, the
defendant had been found not guilty. One of the cases making up this
appeal was a question of law referred by the Attorney General.
4.28
The Court of Appeal dismissed the appeals in R v Quayle on the
basis that none of the defendants had been able to rely at trial on any facts
which could afford them a defence of necessity at common law. The Court
outlined some requirements of any defence of necessity which are indicated by
the common law authorities, and these are as follows: extraneous circumstances
capable of objective scrutiny by judge and jury; an imminent danger of physical
injury; imminence and immediacy. Like Re A (Children)[436] this case centres on medical necessity, as does and so
it is not clear whether a general defence of necessity, based on these
requirements, might exist in English law.
4.29
Necessity has been rejected as a general defence in English law for
several reasons;[437] that it would
cause legal uncertainty, involve judges in difficult policy areas and might
have serious human rights implications.[438] The
decision in R v Dudley and Stephens has also been a major roadblock in
recognising necessity as a general defence in English law.
4.30
In R v Morgenthaler,[439]
a decision of the Supreme Court of Canada, it was noted that “no system of law
can recognize any principle which would entitle a person to violate the law
because on his view the law conflicted with some higher value.”[440]
Williams noted that necessity is invoked equally by despots and rebels,[441]
while other case-law has discussed necessity and noted that it could become
“the mask for anarchy,”[442]
and would “invite the courts to second-guess the legislature and to assess the
relative merits of social policies underlying criminal prohibitions.”[443]
Because of the fear that necessity could be misused if developed as a general
defence, a limited duress of circumstances was developed by the English courts
in a series of road-traffic cases in the late 1980s.[444] In all but
name, duress ‘duress of circumstances’ appears to be a form of defence of
necessity.
4.31
In R v Willer,[445] the
defendant was charged with reckless driving after he had driven very slowly on
a pavement in order to escape from a gang of youths who were intent on doing
violence to him and his passengers. He sought to raise the defence of
necessity but the trial judge did not allow that plea to go to the jury and the
defendant subsequently pleaded guilty. The English Court of Appeal
quashed the conviction on the basis that the defence of duress should have
been left to the jury. It is clear that this marked a departure from the
previous decisions on duress in that the accused was not compelled to act as a
result of any direct threats made by the attackers. Watkins LJ held that
the jury should have been invited to determine whether or not “the appellant
was wholly driven by force
of circumstances into doing what he did.”[446]
4.32
In R v Conway[447] it was noted that, for the sake of convenience, the defence
of duress of which Watkins LJ spoke should be referred to as “duress of
circumstances”. In R v Conway, which also involved a charge of
reckless driving, the defendant drove in a reckless manner in order to escape
two men whom he understood to be attackers. The Court of Appeal followed R
v Willer,
holding that “necessity can only be a defence to a charge of reckless driving
where the facts establish ‘duress of circumstances’”, that is, when the defendant
is constrained by circumstances to drive as he did to avoid death or serious
bodily harm to himself or some other person. Woolf LJ referred to Smith
and Hogan who pointed out that to admit a defence of ‘duress of circumstances’
is a logical consequence of the existence of the defence of duress as that term
is ordinarily understood, that is, ‘do this or else’.[448] He went on to say that this
approach recognises duress as an example of necessity and he referred to Smith
and Hogan stressing that “whether ‘duress of circumstances’ is called ‘duress’
or ‘necessity’ does not matter. What is important is that, whatever it is
called, it is subject to the same limitations as the ‘do this or else’ species
of duress.” The Court cited Lord Hailsham in R v Howe,[449]
who had noted that the distinction between duress and necessity as possible
defences is one which is without, in his Lordships opinion, a relevant
difference, since duress is merely the specific type of necessity caused by
wrongful threats.
4.33
Since duress of circumstances must be subject to the same limitations as
duress, Woolf LJ went on to say that for the defence to be available, the
accused must have been acting in order to avoid a threat of death or serious
injury, and that the defence would be limited by means of an objective
criterion formulated in terms of reasonableness, as laid down by Lord Lane in R v Graham.[450]
In that case the Court of Appeal held, in relation to duress, that the
defendant is required to have the “steadfastness reasonably to be expected of
the ordinary citizen in his situation”.[451] The court in R v Conway indicated
that the defence of duress of circumstances should be subject to this objective
standard. The Court also quashed the conviction.
4.34
Elliot has criticised the use of the objective standard for duress of
circumstances[452]
and argued that in many cases where the defence of duress of circumstances is
raised, the facts are such that self-defence and prevention of crime are just
as analogous as duress.[453]
He suggests that in considering a defence of duress of circumstances it would
be more appropriate to adopt the partly subjective, partly objective, approach
applicable to self-defence and prevention of crime, rather than the wholly
objective approach of duress in
R v Graham.
4.35
In R v Martin[454]
the Court of Appeal went even further in recognising duress of circumstances as
a species of necessity. The defendant, while disqualified from driving,
drove his stepson, who had overslept, to work. He claimed that he had
done this because his wife feared that the stepson would lose his job if he was
late for work and she threatened to commit suicide if he (the defendant) did
not drive the stepson to work. The defendant’s wife had suicidal
tendencies, and there was medical evidence before the trial Court that she
would have carried out the threat of suicide. The Court of Appeal held
that the trial judge ought to have left the defence of duress to the jury and
overturned the conviction.
4.36
Simon Brown LJ stated that English law recognises a defence of necessity
in extreme circumstances – and that where it arises from objective dangers, it
is called duress of circumstances. He adopted the limitations on the
defence as outlined in R v Conway[455] and
R v Graham[456].
The defence is available only if, from an objective standpoint,
the accused can be said to have acted reasonably and proportionately in order
to avoid a threat of death or serious injury. If so, then the jury should
be invited to answer two questions:
· was
the accused impelled to act as he did because, as a result of what he reasonably
believed to be the situation, he had good cause to fear that otherwise death or
serious injury would result, and if so,
· would
a sober person of reasonable firmness, sharing the characteristics of the
accused, have responded to that situation by acting as the accused did?
The court held that if both of these questions can be
answered by the jury in the affirmative, the defence of duress of circumstances
will be established.
4.37
It was once thought that the defence of duress of circumstances might be
restricted in its application to road traffic offences, since it was developed
and used primarily in relation to these cases and it was in fact predicted that
the defence would “experience severe restrictions on its growth”.[457]
One commentator suggested however that since the defence is an extension of the
defence of duress, then, following R v Howe,[458]
it should be applicable in any offence other than murder.[459] It has been pointed out however
that this would constitute a significant change to the law; [460] in fact it has been applied outside the sphere of road
traffic offences.
4.38
In R v Cole,
duress of circumstances was held to be a potential defence to theft.[461]
In R v Pommell,[462]
the defence was applied to unlawful possession of firearms and
ammunition. In R v Pommell, police
officers discovered the defendant in possession of a firearm without a firearms
certificate. The defendant sought to raise the defence of
necessity. He claimed that he had been visited in the early hours by a
friend who intended to kill another person. The defendant had taken the
gun in order to prevent the killing, and had intended handing over the gun to
the police the following day. The trial judge ruled that the defendant’s
failure to go to the police immediately deprived him of the defence. The
defendant was convicted and appealed.
4.39
The Court of Appeal ordered a retrial holding that the trial judge’s
ruling that the defendant’s failure to hand over the gun to the police at the
earliest opportunity effectively denied him the right to have the matter left
to the jury. The Court acknowledged that there is no general defence of
necessity, but accepted the R v Conway position
that necessity can be a defence where the facts establish duress of
circumstances. It was held that regardless of the fact that all the
previous cases establishing duress of circumstances had involved road traffic
offences, the defence was not limited to such cases, and could, because of its
relationship with duress, be applied in relation to “all crimes, except murder
attempted murder, and treason.”[463]
4.40
This was approved by the English Court of Appeal in R v Abdul-Hussain[464]
in which Rose LJ agreed, citing R v Pommell, that the
defence of duress (whether by threats of human or circumstantial origin) was
generally available in relation to all substantive crimes, except murder,
attempted murder and some forms of treason. In this case, the defendants
formed the idea on 8 August 1996 to hijack a plane to avoid being deported to
Iraq where they feared persecution. On 27 August they hijacked a plane
which subsequently landed in England where they were charged with offences
under the UK Aviation Security Act 1982. The trial judge refused
to let the defence of duress go to the jury on the basis that the threat was
insufficiently close and immediate to give rise to a spontaneous reaction to
the risk arising. The Court of Appeal quashed their convictions and held
that the trial judge had interpreted the law in this regard too strictly.
4.41
Rose LJ noted that the decision in R v Martin[465]
afforded the clearest and most authoritative guide to the relevant principles
in relation to both forms of duress. He added that the imminent peril of
death or serious injury to the defendant (or those for whom the defendant has
responsibility) was an essential feature of both forms of duress, and that this
peril must operate in the mind of the defendant at the time when he or she
commits the otherwise criminal act (so as to overbear his will). The
execution of the threat need not, however, be immediately in prospect. He
went on to note that the defence of duress had been developed by the English
courts on a case by case basis and that its scope remained imprecise.
Indeed, it is noteworthy that he emphasised the urgent need for legislation to
define duress with precision.
4.42
To summarise, the English case law indicates that the following criteria
apply to the defence of duress of circumstances:
· an
imminent threat of death or serious injury;
· reasonable
steadfastness in the face of such threats;
· reasonable
grounds for believing in their existence; and
· the
absence of any prior fault on behalf of the defendant.
4.43
The English courts have clearly attempted to develop the defence of
duress of circumstances by analogy with duress. To the extent that they
recognise it as an aspect of necessity, the English courts have outlined its
parameters by aligning it to duress rather than by reference to
necessity.
4.44
In R v Quayle,[466]
the Court of Appeal considered the defence of necessity, which Mance J, at one
point in the judgment, terms “necessity of circumstances.”[467] In looking at the defence of
necessity the Court considered some cases which had been found to involve the
defence of duress of circumstances, including R v Martin,[468] R v Pommell[469] and R v Abdul-Hussain.[470] The Court made reference to Woolf
LJ’s comment in R v Shayler,[471] that “the distinction between duress of
circumstances and necessity has, correctly, been by and large ignored or
blurred by the courts.”[472]
4.45
The Commission concurs with the view that the defence of duress of circumstances
is a defence of necessity in all but name,[473] and one commentator goes as far as to
note that “this conceptual innovation was a substantial step towards
recognising a general defence of necessity by linguistic sleight of hand.”[474]
Because of the continuing impact of the decision in R v Dudley and Stephens,
the English courts have studiously avoided any analogy with necessity,
preferring instead to model duress of circumstances on duress.[475]
4.46
One commentator argues that although the defence itself is a welcome
development, the term duress of circumstances is “clumsy and inappropriate,”[476]
adding that the concept of duress implies a threat or physical danger which
forces a defendant to commit a crime, the threat being “so great as to overbear
the ordinary powers of human resistance.”[477]
4.47
Smith and Hogan however note the danger of treating duress of
circumstances as a defence of necessity, arguing that the stringent
requirements of the defence of duress which it incorporates may inhibit the
development of a broader defence of necessity.[478] Whether duress of circumstances
is related more closely to necessity or duress, it is certainly a recognised
and well-established defence at common law in England.
4.48
The Law Commission considered the defence of necessity in its Working
Paper on the Codification of the Criminal Law: General Principles Defences
of General Application in 1974[479] and the subsequent Report on
Defences of General Application in 1977.[480] It will be necessary to deal with
both these publications as the Report reflects a reversal of policy from the
Working Paper. The Working Paper concluded that a general defence of
necessity is justified provided that it could “be framed in terms which would
obviate its being invoked in extravagant and inappropriate cases.”[481]
Broad policy considerations were discussed and the general defence was proposed
with the following elements. The defence would be available where the
defendant believed that his or her conduct was necessary to avoid some greater
harm. The harm to be avoided should, objectively, be out of proportion to
that caused and need not necessarily be directed against the defendant.
The defence would be available to all offences.
4.49
The Law Commission rejected this general defence in the Report which followed.[482]
It concluded that no attempt should be made by legislation to establish the
defence of necessity, and although improbable, if any such defence exists at
common law the proposed act should abolish it.
4.50
The rationale behind the rejection of the defence was that many issues
arise in relation to the defence of necessity that do not arise with that of
duress. The Report outlined two main differences between the defences of
duress and necessity; first, in cases of duress the source of the harm is
another’s wrongdoing, and second, necessity can be discussed more frequently in
relation to minor offences. As regards the latter difference, the
difficulties with a general defence extending to minor offences outweigh the
advantages. In relation to the former, the Law Commission felt that the
defence of duress is capable of dealing with exceptional and difficult cases in
a way that necessity may not be. Asserting that necessity situations are
not classifiable, the commission expressed doubt as to “whether a defence
operating with such a degree of uncertainty ought to find a place in a Code”.[483]
4.51
The Report on Defences of General Application received much
academic criticism, not least by Williams who suggested that the proposal to
abolish any existing common law defence displayed a misunderstanding of the
rationale of codification. His view was that it shouldn’t be the purpose
of a code to get rid of open-ended defences, or fetter the power of the courts
to create new common law defences.[484]
4.52
The Law Commission’s 1985 Report on the Codification of
the Criminal Law[485]
refers to the recommendations of the 1977 Report. Referring to the
“totally negative” proposals of that Report, the Commission presented two main
criticisms. First, in relation to the analogy with duress, they noted
that the impact of some situations of peril on the persons affected is no
different from that of threats giving rise to a defence of duress.
Reference was made to Cross who had described the proposal to provide for a
defence of duress while excluding the defence of necessity as “the apotheosis
of absurdity.”[486]
The second criticism was in relation to saving the common law, whereby it was
noted that if there is no general defence of necessity, the power of the
judiciary at common law to recognise a situation of necessity as affording a
defence must be preserved.
4.53
The Commission noted that it was satisfied that “[t]he impact of some
situations of imminent peril upon persons affected by them is hardly different
in kind from that of threats such as give rise to the defence of duress.”[487]
4.54
The Law Commission pointed out that necessity doesn’t allow for
restatement, and therefore its main proposal was that necessity should remain a
matter of common law, unaffected by the Criminal Code Act, and the
courts should retain power to clarify and develop the defence. The
Commission did however concede to a general necessity provision in Clause 46,
allowing for the defence in circumstances so obviously analogous to the duress
defence that it would amount to “an apotheosis of absurdity” not to include it.[488]
This provision allows for the defence of necessity (also known as “duress of
circumstances”) if the person does the act believing it to be immediately
necessary to avoid death or serious injury to himself or another, and the
danger he believes to exist is such that in all the circumstances he could not
reasonable be expected to act otherwise. This would apply to all crimes
except murder and attempted murder.[489]
4.55
This defence was again proposed in Clause 43 of the 1989 draft Criminal
Code for England and Wales published by the Law Commission.[490] Rather than refer to the defence
as necessity, the Commission opted to propose the defence of duress of
circumstances, and the accompanying commentary models the defence, as far as is
appropriate, on duress. In the 1989 Commentary on the Code, the
Commission acknowledged criticisms that it had in the past not recognised the
force of the analogy of duress of circumstances with duress, and so placed the
defence under the title of “duress of circumstances.”[491] The Commission recognised the
analogy with duress and acknowledged the need for the defence in the
Code.
4.56
Like duress, duress of circumstances is only applicable in cases of
threat of death or serious personal harm, and is limited by an objective
criterion formulated in terms of reasonableness. The defence does not
apply to murder or attempted murder. This above defence is excusatory in
nature, as was the subsequent defence which proposed in Clause 26 of the Draft
Criminal Law Bill accompanying the 1993 Law Commission Report.[492]
4.57
The 1993 report noted the authority in other common law jurisdictions
for a general defence, and modelled this defence on duress. It proposed a
defence of duress of circumstances in Clause 26 of the Draft Criminal
Law Bill which accompanied the Consultation Paper. Draft Criminal
Code Bill Clause 26 states that a person does not commit an offence if the
act is done under duress of circumstances. The criteria for an act to
satisfy the clause are as follows:
“(a) he does it because he knows or believes that it
is immediately necessary to avoid death or serious personal harm to himself or
another; and
(b) the danger that he knows or believed to exist is
such that in all the circumstances (including any of his personal
characteristics that affect its gravity) he cannot reasonably be expected to
act otherwise.”[493]
4.58
The burden of proof is on the defendant to show that the reason for his
act was such knowledge or belief as is mentioned in paragraph (a). The
section does not apply to those who knowingly and without reasonable excuse
expose themselves to the danger known or believed to exist.
4.59
This provision allows the defence to apply to any offence, which the
Commission recognised would represent a departure from Dudley and Stephens[494]
and from the Draft Criminal Code[495] but which would mirror their
recommendation that duress should apply to all offences.
4.60
The Law Commission has been intent on ensuring that any provisions
proposing the duress of circumstances closely follow the defence of duress of
threats. In the 1993 Report it notes that it was the analogy between
“threats” and other “circumstances” promising an evil unless a crime is
committed that prompted the Court of Appeal to name the new defence “duress of
circumstances” and to model it on duress by adopting the R v Graham test
with modifications.[496]
4.61
The Law Commission acknowledged that duress is often spoken of as if it
is a species of necessity, but that the law may recognise a defence of
“necessity” on a different basis from that underlying duress as a defence.[497]
By contrast with the recognised defences of duress, the Law Commission argued
that there are also cases more properly called cases of necessity, where the
actor does not rely on any allegation that circumstances placed an irresistible
pressure on him but rather claims that his conduct was not unlawful as it was,
in the circumstances, justified.[498] Such claims do require a
comparison between the harm caused and the harm avoided, because if the harm
avoided was not the greater then the law cannot even consider accepting
justification.
4.62
The report pointed to the fact that English courts have not expressly
recognised a general defence of necessity to circumstances where the actor’s
will is not overborne but the conduct is freely adopted, yet the court can
still decide that such conduct is justified.[499] The report goes on to say that as
part of the policy of retention of common law defences, this specific defence
should be left open as something potentially separate from duress, and this is
provided for in the Bill. This is done by the provision of Clause 36(2)
which expressly saves “any distinct defence of necessity” when repealing the
common law defences of duress and duress of circumstances.
4.63
The defence of necessity has been recognised in certain states of
Australia. In Victoria, in the decision in R v Davidson[500] concerning the statutory offence of unlawfully procuring
the miscarriage of a woman, the court ruled, relying on a statement by Stephen
in which the defence of necessity is laid out as an excuse, that there was a
defence of necessity, but added that it was justificatory rather than
excusatory.
4.64
The general, if limited, defence of necessity was recognised in R v
Loughnan,[501]
where it was a defence to escaping from prison, where there was a fear that the
defendant would be killed by the other prisoners. The court relied on the
same statement by Stephen as did the R v Davidson court, but presents
necessity as more of an excuse, outlining the elements involved in the defence
as follows:
“First, the criminal act or acts must have been done
only in order to avoid certain consequences which would have inflicted
irreparable evil upon the accused or upon others whom he was bound to protect…
The [second] element of imminent peril means that
the accused must honestly believe on reasonable grounds that he was placed in a
situation of imminent peril… Thus if there is an interval of time between the
threat and its expected execution it will be rarely if ever that a defence of
necessity can succeed.
The [third] element of proportion simply means that
the acts done to avoid the imminent peril must not be out of proportion to the
peril to be avoided. Put in another way, the test is: would a reasonable
man in the position of the accused have considered that he had any alternative
to doing what he did to avoid the peril?”[502]
4.65
The criminal codes of Western Australia,[503] Queensland[504] and the Northern Territory[505] recognise the defence of “extraordinary
emergency” which is applicable to murder. Under the Commonwealth and ACT
Criminal Codes the defence of sudden or extraordinary emergency is available
where the person reasonably believes:
· Circumstances
of sudden or extraordinary emergency exist;
· Committing
the offence is the only reasonable way to deal with the emergency; and
· The
conduct is a reasonable response to the emergency.[506]
4.66
In 1978, the Law Reform Commission of Victoria published a Working Paper
on Duress, Necessity and Coercion in which it referred to various
criminal codes which incorporate a defence of necessity.[507] This paper made a tentative
recommendation that there should be a general defence of necessity. It
discusses justification and excuse, the bases on which the defence rests.
It notes that the justification-based, choice of evils option is the one used
in the Model Penal Code and the German Penal Code where a legally prohibited act
is justified because it will result in the least harm done to society. It
is then regarded as a lawful act. An excuse-based defence forgives the
actor for an act which is still unlawful, but the doing of which, in the
particular circumstances, renders the actor blameless. This does not
involve the promotion of the greater good. It involves the circumstances
where it may be one life in exchange for another, and the value of the lives
may not be measured, whereby the actor cannot be blamed for his self-preservation
instinct. The working paper contains the provisional suggestion that a
defence of necessity based both on justification and excuse should be provided
by statutory enactment.
4.67
The Report on Duress, Necessity and Coercion was published two
years later.[508]
It noted that there is no comprehensive statement of principle in relation to
necessity nor has the defence any reliable precision of definition and goes on
state that “[A] rational and humane system of law should take into account that
there will always be situations where to insist on the strict letter of the law
would create injustice and justifiably breed resentment of the law.”[509]
The report recommends the provision for the exculpation of conduct which can be
justified by necessity. This takes into account three requirements - the
harm avoided must be greater than the harm caused, there must be no
alternative, less harmful and reasonable means of avoiding harm, and the danger
of harm must be imminent. It is noted in the report that this raises two
immediate problems, as it is a choice of evils scenario. The first
problem is whether murder can ever be justified and the second is who decides
whether the benefit exceeds the cost?
4.68
The Report ultimately recommended a general defence of necessity based
upon the principle of justification by choosing the lesser evil. This
defence would be available where the defendant believes his conduct is
necessary to avoid imminent injury to person or property. The
desirability of avoiding the injury should clearly outweigh the injury
prevented by the law governing the offence, according to ordinary standards of
intelligence and morality.[510]
4.69
The Report also recommended an excuse-based defence of “duress of
circumstances” or “necessity which excuses”.[511] The Commission acknowledged the
clear need for a new dimension of excuse to be recognised and for the principle
behind the defence of duress to be extended to situations where the accused is
compelled by circumstances, whether of human or non-human origin.
4.70
Three situations were outlined for which there is a need for a defence
of duress or necessity. These are:
·
Where there is a threat from another that the actor or another will
suffer harm if the demand for criminal action is not met – this is dealt with
by the law of duress;
·
Where there is a threat of harm from another with no demand for criminal
action but criminal action is nevertheless taken to avoid the harm - necessity
can be used, but the report suggested that this would be done uneasily.
It would seem that a choice of the lesser evils must be discovered for it to
succeed;
·
Where there is a threat from inanimate circumstances. This would
cover bizarre and rare cases such as R v Dudley and Stephens[512] where the instinct of self-preservation is an
issue. It can be said that a choice of evils may never be said to justify
the killing of another human being, but in such a case, “to excuse such conduct
is not to say that it was right or justifiable, but to realise that there can
be a point at which normal or ordinary or reasonable human conduct can no
longer be expected.”[513]
4.71
As noted below, the German Penal Code embraces all three of the above
situations,[514]
and the Report suggests that if the necessity recommendation is acceptable then
it seems simpler, tidier and more convenient to widen the ambit of duress to
embrace them. The Commission then goes on to recommend a duress defence
which will cover compulsion, whether of human origin or arising from
circumstances surrounding the commission of the offence.[515]
4.72
In 1991, the Law Reform Commission of Victoria suggested that necessity
is similar to duress, except that the source of the compulsion is impersonal.[516]
It went on to note that even if necessity is accepted as a general defence, it
is doubtful that the defence applies to murder and uses R v Dudley and
Stephens[517]
as authority on this point.
4.73
In the 2004 Report on Defences to Homicide, the Law Reform
Commission of Victoria discussed the defences of duress and extraordinary
emergency under the Model Criminal Code.[518] This allows, as a defence to any
offence, the defence of sudden or extraordinary emergency, where the person
reasonably believes:
· Circumstances
of sudden or extraordinary emergency exist;
· Committing
the offence is the only reasonable way to deal with the emergency; and
· The
conduct is a reasonable response to the emergency.[519]
4.74
The report goes on to discuss the arguments for applying duress and
necessity to murder and the arguments for necessity are similar to those for
duress. It notes that a person should not be criminally liable, if in the
face of extraordinary emergency and an agonising choice between evils, he or
she acts reasonably. The Commission recommended that the Crimes Act
1958 be amended to make it clear that duress and necessity are defences to
murder and attempted murder.[520]
It also recommends that a person shall not be held criminally responsible for
murder or manslaughter if the persons conduct is a response to circumstances of
sudden or extraordinary emergency.[521] This defence is only available in
the above circumstances.
4.75
In Canada, the Supreme Court considered the defence of necessity in R
v Perka.[522]
It concluded that necessity may be an “excuse” but not a “justification” for an
act which is “inevitable, unavoidable and afford[s] no reasonable opportunity
for an alternative course of action that does not involve a breach of the law.”[523]
This judgment appears to be an endorsement of the defence on an excusatory
basis.
4.76
Although the doctrine of necessity exists in Canada, it is clear from
such cases as R v Perka,[524] R v Morgenthaler[525] and R v Latimer[526]
that its scope is narrow. In the latter two cases, it is apparent that
Canadian courts see it as very unlikely that the defence of necessity will be
available in cases where the taking of innocent life is involved. The Perka requirements
were that in order for necessity to be accepted as a defence the act must be
inevitable, unavoidable and the situation must afford no reasonable opportunity
for an alternative course of action.
4.77
In R v Morgenthaler
it was held that there was no evidence that there was a necessity for the
defendant, a doctor, to carry out a number of unlawful abortions, rather that the
defendant considered the law against the act to be objectionable. The
Court formed no very clear foundation for the defence of necessity and with the
exception of Laskin CJC dissenting, did not give the defence much import or
treat the defence as a general defence to criminal liability.
4.78
In R v Latimer,
the Court relied heavily on R v Perka. Here,
it was decided that the requirements of the doctrine of necessity were not
satisfied by a man who killed his daughter, a cerebral palsy sufferer.
The court reinforced the R v Perka requirement
of urgency, as well as the requirement that there be no reasonable alternative
to breaking the law. These were both “modified objective” tests, the
belief being reasonable, but as measured by a reasonable person with the
characteristics and in the situation of specific accused. The court held,
on the facts that there was no emergency situation, and there was in fact a
reasonable alternative. The third requirement was wholly objective -
being that the belief that the harm avoided was greater than the harm of
breaking the law was one that must be held by society rather than the
individual accused. In this case the court felt that ending pain where
the pain is medically manageable is not proportionate. The court noted, obiter, that “[i]t is
difficult at the conceptual level, to imagine a circumstance in which the
proportionality requirement could be met for a homicide.”[527]
4.79
The Canadian Law Reform Commission dealt with the defence of necessity
in the 1982 Working Paper on Criminal Law: The General Part - Liability and
Defences.[528]
It noted the four possible approaches to a situation where necessity arises:
· The
defendant can be convicted with no note taken of the extenuating circumstances;
·
The defendant may be convicted with the judge having discretion in
relation to sentencing. The Commission noted that while this allows
flexibility, it may still be unfair, as the actor would still be found guilty
when morally he is not guilty. The Commission pointed out that the law
would be convicting him with one hand and letting him off with the other.
It was also argued that leaving it to judicial discretion could undermine the
rule of law;
· The
law could leave it to prosecutorial discretion. It was noted by the
Commission that this would however result in a lack of development of
jurisprudence, and a divergence between law in code and law in practice;
· The
law could provide a defence of necessity. This could be done either
section-by-section for specific instances, or a general rule. The paper
argues that the latter is more preferable as the former would be too detailed
and complicated.
4.80
The paper refers to the clear rationale of necessity, and notes that it
involves two factors. These are the avoidance of greater harm or the pursuit
of a greater good, and the difficulty of compliance with law in
emergencies. The two principles emerging are the utilitarian idea of
justification and the humanitarian one of excuse.
4.81
A justificatory defence is included in the draft legislation. This
states that “everyone is excused from criminal liability for an offence
committed out of necessity arising from circumstances other than unlawful
threat or attack,” as long as he acts to avoid immediate harm to persons and property,
and that harm substantially outweighs the harm caused by the offence, and the
harm couldn’t have been avoided by lesser means.
4.82
The humanitarian principle to which the Commission refers is that the
law should not ask more of ordinary individuals than can be fairly asked of
people of ordinary courage, strength and fortitude. The Commission
suggests that refusal of the law to make concessions for those who were faced
with overwhelming pressures would be “unfair, unrealistic and inconsistent.”[529]
4.83
The phrase “substantially outweighs” in the draft clause rules out the
use of the defence in “life for life” cases such as R v Dudley and Stephens.[530]
The Commission suggests that in such cases the use of discretion of
prosecutors, courts, juries and cabinets could be used to conclude that in the
circumstances the defendants own life would have seemed to him to have
substantially outweighed the other persons. The Commission comes to the
conclusion that although it involves a derogation from the rule of law this
seems the most appropriate way to deal with these difficult and rare cases.
4.84
In 1987, the Commission proposed a necessity clause in its report on Recodifying
Criminal Law.[531]
This was very similar to the clause proposed in the working paper, and contains
a general rule, as per the Working Paper, and also has an exception that states
that the clause does not apply to anyone who himself purposely kills or
seriously harms another person.[532] This clause incorporates and
codifies the rule laid down in R v Perka[533]
by the Supreme Court of Canada. As at common law, the defence is not
available to murder, and the Commission added a proviso similar to the one
relating to duress whereby a person may not rely on the defence if he purposely
kills or seriously harms another person.
4.85
A defence of necessity has been recognised in South Africa.[534]
In South Africa, for an act to be justified on the ground of necessity, five
requirements must be met:
· A
legal interest of the accused must have been endangered;
· The
threat must have commenced or be imminent;
· The
accused must not bear any responsibility for the duress;
· The
actions taken must have been reasonably necessary for the accuse to avert the
danger; and
· The
means used for this purpose must have been reasonable in the circumstances.[535]
4.86
German law takes the approach of recognising two separate kinds of
necessity, distinguishing, in the German Federal Penal Code, between justifying
necessity[536]
and excusable necessity.[537] This
approach has attracted a certain degree of academic support,[538]
and it has been noted that the introduction of one defence covering the
existing defences would have the advantage of removing certain anomalies that
exist at present due to current classifications. It would also resolve
controversy as to whether necessity exists as a defence and clarify its
relationship with the defence of duress of circumstances.[539]
4.87
The first part of the German Penal Code, justifying necessity, allows a
person to be justified in their actions it they commit an act in order to
protect a superior
legal interest from imminent peril.[540]
A clear case of lesser evils, this defence recognises that the actions of the
accused would be unlawful if they do not involve averting an imminent and
otherwise unavoidable danger. The actions are seen as the appropriate
means to a lawful end. Thus the act committed is not unlawful, but
justified. The chief characteristic of the defence is the proportion
between harms - in cases of a life for a life this defence cannot be
used. This section cannot be used to justify the killing of another human,
even when there are more human lives saved by the sacrifice of one. Some
German writers recognise an exception in the case of joint risky ventures, such
as rock climbing expeditions, in which it may be necessary to kill one member
of the party to save others.[541]
However if the approach taken in R v Dudley and Stephens[542]
were applied it is likely that justification would be denied in such cases.
4.88
The second element of the German Penal Code states that whoever commits
an unlawful act in order to avert an imminent and otherwise unavoidable danger
to his own life, limb or liberty, or to that of a relative, or person close to
him acts without guilt.[543] But
rather than the act being justified, their actions are excused. This
defence is less limited in its application as there is no requirement of a
weighing of interests. The classic example of this section in action is
that of two sailors each seeking to overthrow the other from a plank that will
only hold one of them. The one who removes the other to save his own life
cannot have his actions justified, but can be excused, according to the second
element of the German Penal Code. It is suggested that the rationale
behind this could be either of 2 approaches - psychological and normative.[544]
In the psychological approach, the actor’s blameworthiness is reduced by the
extraordinary stress of the situation and his commendable intention to save a
legal interest. The normative approach recognises that punishment in this
situation would yield no legitimate penological benefits.[545]
4.89
The defence of duress is not specifically included in the German Penal
Code as such cases would generally be covered by the necessity sections.
It has however been pointed out that there are difficult cases of duress which
are not covered by these provisions, and that as a result, duress has been left
in a “no-man’s land between justification and excuse.”[546]
4.90
It has been noted[547]
that the distinction between justification and excuse is also firmly entrenched
in the analytical architecture of another civilian criminal code, the Italian Codice
Penale. Italian law treats duress as a species of the larger genus of
necessity. In cases of lesser evils, necessity is a complete defence, on
the grounds that the defendant has made the right choice in difficult
circumstances not of his own making. Where the defendant cannot claim to
have chosen the lesser of two evils, the plea of necessity fails completely,
although the courts are at liberty to give effect to the element of compulsion
at the sentencing stage. The Italian distinction between justificatory
excusatory defences differs in a number of significant respects from its German
counterpart. But in the specific context of the defence of necessity, the Codice
Penale shares the German view that necessity is justificatory in nature –
by contrast, the common law conception of necessity is excusatory in
nature. While the Commission acknowledges the pre-eminence of the
excusatory approach to necessity in the common law tradition, it sees merit in
leaving open the possibility, in particular in the context of codification,[548]
that the different architecture adopted in the Codice Penale is also
worthy of consideration.
4.91
Necessity has also been provided for to an extent in a number of other
criminal codes. These include the Indian Penal Code[549] and the Australian Model Criminal Code,[550]
as well as the German Federal Penal Code.[551] In the Scottish Law Commission’s
2003 Draft Criminal Code for Scotland necessity is recognised as a defence, if
the acts done are “immediately necessary and reasonable in order to prevent a
greater harm… and the commission of what would otherwise be an offence could
reasonably be regarded as justifiable in the circumstances”.[552] This is only if the acts are done
in order to save a human life.
4.92
Williams believes however that the best formulation of the defence of
necessity is to be found in The American Law Institute’s Model Penal Code,
which provides that:
“conduct which the actor believes to be necessary to
avoid an evil to himself or another is justifiable, provided that… the evil sought
to be avoided by such conduct is greater than that sought to be prevented by
the law defining the offense charged…”[553]
4.93
It has been suggested that duress should be regarded as an excusatory
defence, while necessity should be seen as justificatory. If there is an
element of choice of evil in the necessity defence then the defendant can argue
that he or she took the best course of action in difficult circumstances and
that the defendant’s actions are justified rather than wrong but excusable.
This point of distinction between the two defences was emphasised by the Law
Commission of England and Wales in its Report on Offences Against
the Person and General Principles:[554]
“By contrast with the defences of duress… there
appear to be some cases, more properly called cases of ‘necessity’ where the
actor does not rely on any allegation that circumstances placed an irresistible
pressure on him. Rather, he claims that his conduct, although falling
within the definition of an offence, was not harmful because it was, in the
circumstances, justified. Such claims, unlike those recognised by the
duress defences, do seem to require a comparison between the harm that the
otherwise unlawful conduct has caused and the harm that that conduct has
avoided; because if the latter harm was not regarded as the greater the law
could not even consider accepting that the conduct was justified. Nor,
fairly clearly, does the defence depend on any claim that the actor’s will was
‘overborne’: on the contrary the decision to do what, but for the exceptional
circumstances, would be a criminal act may be the result of a careful
judgment…”[555]
This
approach chimes well with the Law Commission’s view that, in contrast to
necessity, the duress defences normally operate on an excusatory basis.
4.94
In Irish and English case-law, the Commission notes that the terms
justification and excuse have been used almost interchangeably by the courts.[556]
Examples given include Murnaghan J’s alternate use of justification and excuse
in Attorney General v Whelan[557] and Lord Wilberforce’s synomonous use of the two terms
in the same paragraph in DPP for Northern Ireland v Lynch[558]. The
Commission considers that in R v Howe[559] the confusion appears to have been overcome, although
parts of the judgment belie a degree of misunderstanding of the nature of the
terms.
4.95
The Canadian Supreme Court in R v Perka[560]
recognised that necessity could be conceptualised as either a justification or
as an excuse but that in Canada it should be operated as an excuse.
Dickson J noted that this concedes that the act was wrongful, but withholds
criminal attribution to the person because of the dire circumstances
surrounding the person at the time of the commission of the crime. He
summarised the rationale of necessity by noting that “[a]t the heart of this
defence is the perceived injustice of punishing violations of the law in
circumstances in which the person had no other viable or reasonable choice
available; the act was wrong but it is excused because it was unavoidable.”[561]
4.96
Some commentators have argued that the distinction between justification
and excuse is irrelevant, on the grounds that no significant legal consequences
flow from it, and indeed Walker LJ in Re A (Children) stated
in relation to defences of necessity “I do not think it matters whether these
defences are regarded as justifications or excuses”.[562]
4.97
In some jurisdictions the distinction is not regarded as important and
in South Africa, necessity may be an excusatory defence or a justificatory one,
depending on the circumstances.[563] As noted above, the German Penal
Code also distinguishes between justifiable and excusable necessity,
recognising them as two separate kinds of necessity.[564]
4.98
However, it has been pointed out that acquittals are not always neutral
in respect of the issue of justification and excuse.[565] The basis for an acquittal can be
of some importance when discussing criminal liability. For example, in
the context of legitimate defence, it is clear from an acquittal that a
defendant has a right to use force in the face of unlawful attack. An acquittal
in these circumstances implies that his or her actions were consistent with the
fundamental objectives of the criminal law.
4.99
The Commission acknowledges that a defensible case can be made for
treating the plea of necessity as either a justification or an
excuse, depending on the circumstances of the case. At the same time the
Commission acknowledges the pre-eminence of the excusatory approach to
necessity in the common law tradition; and, while provisionally recommending
the adoption of that approach in Ireland, also invites submissions on the
viability of the justificatory approach.
4.100
The Commission provisionally recommends that the defence of necessity
be continued on its traditional excusatory basis. However, the Commission
also accepts that there is a defensible case for treating the defence of
necessity as a justification, and accordingly invites submissions on this
point.
4.101
As already noted, in England the defence of duress of circumstances
covers any situations in which necessity might be used as a defence.
4.102
It is rare that cases arise in which the facts call for the use of a
defence of necessity. However, it is arguable that a defence of necessity would
be more appropriate than duress of circumstances in those cases which do
occur. This would mean that the defence would be explicitly outlined in
the law, rather than allowing inappropriate defence labels to be used, or
allowing the case simply to be left to prosecutorial discretion. The
Commission appreciates that leaving cases to the prosecutorial discretion
system ensures that those who should not be charged with certain offences are
not so charged.
4.103
In the case of the Zeebrugge situation, the facts of which are discussed
above,[566]
a decision was made not to prosecute the person who had removed another person
from a ladder to which he was frozen with fear, in order to save the lives of
many more. It is likely that had a case been initiated the defence of
necessity would have sufficed to excuse the person involved, but it is
appreciated that the fact that prosecutorial discretion was exercised in this
case also led to an appropriate outcome.
4.104
Chapter 3 of this Consultation Paper discussed in detail the possibility
of allowing duress to be a defence in homicide cases. It also outlined
the advantages and disadvantages of extending duress to murder, both as a full
defence and as a partial defence.
4.105
The argument in favour of extending duress to murder also applies to
necessity. To the extent that it is accepted that the law should make a
concession to human frailty in the case of someone who kills under extreme
moral compulsion, it is difficult to resist the conclusion that the application
of this principle should not be made to turn on the accident of whether the
threats faced by the defendant were human rather than circumstantial.
Similarly, to the extent that it is accepted that duress should be made
available as a form of lesser evils in murder cases, there is no reason in
principle why the same logic should not be applied to necessity.
4.106
Clearly, the availability of necessity to a murder charge is one which
has broad legal and moral ramifications. The authority of R v Dudley
and Stephens[567]
appears to be entrenched and has cast what has been referred to as an
“unhelpful shadow” on subsequent decisions on necessity.[568] However, noting the apparent
acceptance, albeit limited, of the defence in certain cases, along with the
emergence and development of the defence of duress of circumstances, many
commentators have come to believe that the defence of necessity could in fact
be relied upon in extreme circumstances. An example cited by Smith and
Hogan regarding the destruction of the World Trade Centre is that that necessity
may have been a defence to murder had one of the planes been shot down, killing
all of the passengers, but preventing a much greater disaster. [569]
Here the suggestion is that necessity may even be a defence to murder, but this
opinion is without authority.
4.107
It has been suggested that it may be possible to introduce in Ireland a
defence of duress of circumstances which can incorporate the current defence of
necessity. However, the defence of duress of circumstances was only
introduced in English law to allow a defence to be pleaded which in effect is a
defence of necessity. Thus, there is no need for such a defence to be
introduced in Ireland because a defence of necessity could equally be developed.
4.108
Section 18(3) of the Non Fatal Offences Against the Person Act 1997,
which deals with the justifiable use of force against a criminal act, provides
that such an act will be deemed to have occurred even where the actor would
have a defence on grounds of “duress, whether by threats or of
circumstances.” It has been tentatively suggested that this would seem to
indicate legislative acceptance of the defence of duress of circumstances, but
such a defence has not been recognised by the Irish courts, and it remains
unclear as to whether this constitutes legislative acceptance of the defence.
4.109
The Commission is of the opinion that the defence of duress of
circumstances is a defence of necessity in all but name and makes no
recommendation on the possibility of introducing a defence of duress of
circumstances in Irish law. Rather, it is recommended that a defence of
necessity exist for cases which might come under the scope of duress of
circumstances.
4.110
Necessity is a defence which excuses the behaviour of the person who
committed what would otherwise have been a crime, if it were not for the
constrained choice which the person faced in the circumstances. It is
therefore the opinion of the Commission that the defence of necessity should
co-exist with duress, and that there should be no need for a further defence of
duress of circumstances.
4.111
Whether this defence is termed necessity or duress of circumstances, it
has been pointed out that in effect there is a limited general defence of
necessity in existence in English (and possibly Irish) law.[570] One commentator has ventured to
say that it is difficult to see how a return to the ancient defence of
necessity can be avoided.[571]
However, it has also been suggested that the development of the necessity
defence will be inextricably linked with the defence of duress, so much so that
there is now merely “a remote likelihood that the defence of necessity as a
full blown plea of lesser evils will be recognised.”[572]
4.112
There is the possibility that a defence of necessity be introduced that
is based on a plea of lesser evils, similar to section 34 of the German Federal
Penal Code on justifying necessity.[573] This would involve an element of
choice, albeit the choice would still be constrained. The defence would
involve the recognition that there are two courses of action which may be taken
and the person then chooses the one which results in the least overall
harm. A rational choice is made which arguably results in the more
preferable outcome. It has been suggested that making a choice of this
kind surely “conforms with what a rational legal system ought to regard as the
preferred outcome in these circumstances”.[574]
4.113
In relation to choice of evils, it is, of course, difficult to establish
how a decision that the choice was the ‘right choice’ should be made. If
there is no life lost then a simple weighing up of interests may be done. If
life is lost, and this defence is applicable to homicide cases, then it is arguable
that a weighing up of interests may not be done, due to the sanctity of human
life. However, it has been suggested that where there is no need to
select a victim, that is, the victim selects himself, and there is a net saving
of human life, for example, the person on the ladder in the Zeebrugge
situation, then such a principle may be used. It seems that the evils
avoided outweighs that caused, - one dies instead of many - and so it has been
argued that it is right that a defence should exist in these circumstances.[575]
4.114
The distinction between this defence of lesser evils and the defence of
necessity as dealt with throughout this chapter is that with the latter defence
it is not necessary that the individual weigh up the choices involved, it is
merely that the person has committed the crime because he or she was compelled
by the circumstances to do so.
4.115
In relation to the labelling of the defence of necessity, it is possible
that it may be developed under different nomenclature. Because the
defence of duress of circumstances was introduced as a result of the pejorative
status which the term “necessity” has attracted in England, it may be more
appropriate to develop the defence of necessity under a different
heading.
4.116
The Commission is of the opinion that this area is one which will need a
good deal of consideration during the consultation process. It is with
this in mind that the Commission would particularly invite submissions on this
defence and a potential defence of lesser evils. For the purposes of this
Consultation Paper, the Commission provisionally recommends that a defence of necessity should apply in those situations
where duress does not apply and that it would apply in certain exceptional
circumstances. This defence would be available in situations where a person is
faced with a constrained choice regarding his or her actions, the constraint
arising from extraneous circumstances, and where the person, in choosing the
course of action taken, breaks the law.
4.117
The Commission provisionally recommends that a defence of necessity
should apply in those situations where duress does not apply and that it would
apply in certain exceptional circumstances. This defence would be available in
situations where a person is faced with a constrained choice regarding his or
her actions, the constraint arising from extraneous circumstances, and where
the person, in choosing the course of action taken, breaks the law.
5
5.01
The provisional recommendations contained in this Paper may be
summarised as follows:
5.02
The Commission provisionally recommends that the status of the defence
of duress as an excusatory defence in general terms should be retained.
[Paragraph 2.24]
5.03
The Commission provisionally recommends that the threat which underpins
the defence of duress should be one of death or serious harm. [Paragraph
2.49]
5.04
The Commission provisionally recommends that the defence of duress
should be available where a threat of death or serious harm is directed towards
any person and that there should be no restriction in the availability of the
defence in relation to the target of the threats. [Paragraph 2.61]
5.05
The Commission provisionally recommends that, in establishing whether
the response of the accused was a reasonable one, an objective test should be
applied. [Paragraph 2.97]
5.06
The Commission provisionally recommends that the belief in the
existence, nature and seriousness of the threats should be reasonably held and
that the test should be what an ordinary person with the accused’s
characteristics would have reasonably believed in the circumstances.
[Paragraph 2.106]
5.07
The Commission provisionally recommends that while the threat should be
imminent, no requirement of immediacy should exist in relation to the harm
threatened. [Paragraph 2.135]
5.08
The Commission provisionally recommends that the person threatened
should be required to seek official protection if possible but that a failure
to do so will not automatically preclude the availability of the defence.
[Paragraph 2.136]
5.09
The Commission provisionally recommends that a person who seeks to avail
of the defence of duress may not do so if they ought reasonably to have
foreseen the likelihood of being subjected to threats, for example, by
voluntarily joining a criminal organisation which subsequently puts pressure on
the person to commit offences. [Paragraph 2.159]
5.10
The Commission provisionally recommends that the defence of marital
coercion should be formally abolished by statute, and notes that the defence of
duress is available to any person who is threatened by their spouse or partner.
[Paragraph 2.181]
5.11
The Commission provisionally recommends that the onus should remain on
the prosecution to disprove the defence of duress beyond a reasonable doubt.
[Paragraph 2.192]
5.12
The Commission provisionally recommends that the defence of duress
should apply to all offences excluding murder and attempted murder.
Moreover, while acknowledging that the plea might be made available as a
partial defence to those offences, the Commission accepts that a coherent case
can also be made for treating duress as a complete defence where the accused’s
actions can be justified on the grounds of lesser evils, and invites
submissions on this matter. [Paragraph 3.102]
5.13
The Commission provisionally recommends that the defence of necessity be
continued on its traditional excusatory basis. However, the Commission
also accepts that there is a defensible case for treating the defence of
necessity as a justification, and accordingly invites submissions on this
point. [Paragraph 4.101]
5.14
The Commission provisionally recommends that a defence of necessity
should apply in those situations where duress does not apply and that it would
apply in certain exceptional circumstances. This defence would be available in
situations where a person is faced with a constrained choice regarding his or
her actions, the constraint arising from extraneous circumstances, and where
the person, in choosing the course of action taken, breaks the law. [Paragraph
4.119]
[1]
The Commission’s Second
Programme of Law Reform 2000-2007, identified defences including
provocation, legitimate defence and duress and necessity as areas for
examination.
[2]
Law Reform Commission Consultation
Paper on Homicide: the Plea of Provocation (LRC CP 27-2003) at 1. See also Report
of the Expert Group on the Codification of the Criminal Law: Codifying
the Criminal Law (Department of Justice, Equality and Law Reform 2004).
[3]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000) Chapter 17.
[4]
Ibid.
[5]
Duress per minas may
be translated as duress by menaces and is referred to in this Consultation
Paper as duress.
[6]
See paragraphs
2.25-2.49. For a more detailed discussion of duress, see Chapters 2 and 3
below.
[7]
See paragraphs
2.62-2.106 below.
[8]
[1934] IR 518. See discussion at paragraph
2.03 below.
[9]
See also paragraph 4.04
below.
[10]
See R v Shayler [2001] 1 WLR 2206, discussed at paragraph
4.08 below.
[11]
[1934] IR 518. It was not until the
early 1940s that the Irish law reports adopted the current convention of
entitling prosecutions on indictment as being in the name of The People.
[12]
Ibid.
[13]
[1934] IR 518, 521. See paragraph 2.27
below.
[14]
Ibid, 524.
[15]
Ibid, 526.
[16]
Ibid. In DPP
for Northern Ireland v Lynch [1975] AC 653, Lord Morris noted in relation
to the Whelan case that the word ‘excuse’ would have been more
appropriate than ‘justification’. See paragraph 4.94 below.
[17]
See paragraph 3.02
below.
[18] For
example, R v Hasan [2005] 4 All ER 685, R v Howe [1987] AC 417, R v Harding [1976] VR
129, DPP for Northern Ireland v Lynch [1975] AC 653, R v Smyth [1963] VR
737.
[19]
The defence was dealt
with in The People (DPP) v Kavanagh Court of Criminal Appeal 18 May 1999
but only in order to establish the onus of proof in relation to the
defence. See paragraph 2.182 below.
[20]
Court of Criminal Appeal 7
March 2003.
[21]
The Court ordered a retrial on
the basis that the trial judge had not directed the jury correctly in relation
to the burden of proof. See paragraph 2.184 below.
[22]
[2005] 4 All ER 685, 694-695.
[23]
See paragraphs 2.137-2.159
above.
[24]
R v Hasan [2005] 4 All ER 685, 695.
[25]
See paragraph 4.29-4.47.
[26]
[1967] VR 526.
[27]
Fisse Howard’s Criminal Law
(5th ed The Lawbook Company 1990) at 541.
[28]
Fletcher “The
Individualisation of Excusing Conditions” (1974) 47 S Cal LR 1269 at 1308.
[29]
The issue of justification and
excuse in relation to the defence of necessity is discussed at paragraphs 4.93-
4.100 below.
[30]
Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 1086.
[33]
See paragraph
[34]
[1934] IR 518. See paragraph 2.03 above.
[35]
Williams Criminal Law: The
General Part (2nd ed Stevens and Sons Ltd 1961) at 751.
[36]
See R v Hudson and Taylor [1971] 2 QB 202 and R v Graham [1982] 1 All ER 801.
[37]
[1947] KB 997.
[39]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Report on Defences of General Application (No 83
1977).
[40]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Codification of the Criminal Law (No 143 1986) at
paragraph 13.15 to 13.24. Draft Criminal Code Bill 1985 clause 45.
[41]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Codification of the Criminal Law (No 143 1986) at
paragraph 15.43.
[42]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: A Criminal Code for England and Wales Volume 2:
Commentary on Draft Criminal Code Bill (No 177 1989) at paragraph 12.14.
[43]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences Against the
Person and General Principles (No 218 1993) at paragraph 29.1.
[44]
RS 1985 c. C-46; s.17 RS 1985,
c 27 (1st Supp) s.40.
[45]
Law Reform Commission of
Canada Criminal Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences (Working
Paper 29 1982) at 87.
[46]
Law Reform Commission of
Canada Report: Recodifying Criminal Law (No 30 Volume 1 1986) at 32-33.
[47]
Ibid at 32.
[48]
[1967] VR 526.
[49]
R v Harding [1976] VR
129, R v Lawrence [1980] 1 NSWLR 122, although this threat was not
recognised in R v Foster (1990) 14 Crim LJ 289.
[50]
Dennis “Duress, Murder and
Criminal Responsibility” (1980) 96 LQR 208 at 231.
[51]
Yeo Compulsion in the
Criminal Law (The Law Book Company Ltd 1990) at 71.
[52]
Section 31 Criminal Code (WA);
section 31 Criminal Code (Qd); section 20(1) Criminal Code Act 1924.
[53]
Victorian Law Reform
Commission Duress, Necessity and Coercion (No 9 1980) at paragraph 4.19.
[54]
Criminal Law Officers
Committee of the Standing Committee of Attorneys-General Model Criminal
Code: Chapters 1 and 2: General Principles of Criminal Responsibility
(1992) at 65.
[55]
Victorian Law Reform
Commission Defences to Homicide: Final Report (2004) at paragraph 3.156;
Recommendation 13.
[56]
[2001] NZLR 431.
[57]
S v Goliath (1972) 3 SA
1. See paragraphs 3.60 and 4.85 below.
[58]
R v Metwa (1921) TPD
227; R v Chansie (1926) OPD 74.
[59]
R v Canestra (1951) 2
SA 317.
[60]
R v Vermaak (1900) 21
NLR 204 at 211.
[61]
Burchell and Hunt South
African Criminal Law and Procedure Volume 1: General Principles of Criminal Law
(3rd ed Juta 1997) at 89.
[62]
Commonwealth v Refitt 149
Ky 300 (1912) at 303-4.
[63]
Perryman v State 63 Ga
App 819, 12 SE 2d 388 (1940).
[64]
[1975] AC 653 at 687-688. Lord Simon
discussed the issue of who the threat must be directed to and went on to
discuss threats to property, noting that a threat of injury to property is not
enough to found the defence as the line has to be drawn somewhere, however
anomalous.
[65]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Codification of the Criminal Law; General Principles: Defences of
General Application (No 55 1974) at paragraph 16.
[66]
Fisse Howard’s Criminal Law
(5th ed The Law Book Company 1990) at 551.
[67]
Interestingly, the balancing of harms approach does receive some support from
Hale, Pleas of the Crown i 56.
[68]
[1934] IR 518. See paragraph 2.03
above.
[69]
[1954] IR 12.
[70]
R v Conway [1989] QB 290; R v Martin [1989] 1 All ER 652.
[72]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences Against the Person
and General Principles (No 218 1993) at paragraph 29.2.
[73]
Law Reform Commission of
Canada Criminal Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences (No 29
1982) at 87 reads: “Every one is excused from criminal liability for an offence
committed by way of reasonable response to threats of serious and immediate
bodily harm to himself or those under his protection unless his conduct
manifestly endangers life or seriously violates bodily integrity.”
[74]
Law Reform Commission of
Canada Report: Recodifying Criminal Law Volume 1 (No 30 1986) at 32
reads: “No one is liable for committing a crime in reasonable response to
threats of immediate serious harm to himself or another person unless he
himself purposely causes the death of, or seriously harms, another person.”
[75]
R v Hurley and Murray [1967]
VR (FC) 526.
[76]
Victorian Law Reform
Commission Duress, Necessity and Coercion (No 9 1980) at paragraph 4.19.
[77]
Victorian Law Reform
Commission Defences to Homicide: Final Report (2004) at paragraph 3.155.
[78]
See paragraph 2.51 in relation
to The People (AG) v Keatley [1954] IR 12.
[79]
Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 1090.
[80]
[1934] IR 518. See paragraph 2.03
above.
[81]
Ibid, 526.
[82]
Court of Criminal Appeal 7
March 2003.
[83]
[1975] 1 All ER 913, 952.
[85]
[1987] All ER 771.
[87]
Lord Lane CJ expressly
excluded transitory, self induced factors such as drink or drugs.
[88]
In DPP v Camplin [1978] AC 705 the House of Lords held that
the jury may take into account those characteristics of the accused which bear
on the gravity of the provocation to him.
[90]
[1994] Crim LR 353.
[91]
[1994] Crim LR 584.
[92]
[2005] 4 All ER 685, 695. See
paragraph 2.15 above.
[93]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Report on Defences of General Application (No 83
1977) at paragraph 2.28.
[94]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Codification of the Criminal Law A Report to the Law
Commission (No 143 1986) at paragraph 13.15 to 13.24. Clause 45 Draft
Criminal Code Bill 1985.
[95]
See clause 1(3) of the Draft
Bill.
[96]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: A Criminal Code for England and Wales Volume 1: Report
and Draft Criminal Code Bill and Volume 2: Commentary on Draft Criminal
Code Bill (No 177 1989).
[97]
Clause 42(3)(b) Draft
Criminal Code Bill.
[98]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences Against the
Person and General Principles (No 218 1993).
[99]
Law Commission of England and
Wales A New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005).
[100]
See paragraph 3.27-3.30 below.
[101]
Law Commission of England and
Wales A New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005) at
paragraph 7.39.
[102]
Ibid at paragraph 7.2.
[104]
Ibid, 806.
Emphasis added.
[105]
See for example DPP v
Rogers [1998] Crim LR 202.
[108]
Ibid, 691.
[109]
Ibid, 696.
[110]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences Against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993).
[111]
Ibid at paragraph 29.9.
[112]
Law Commission of England and Wales A
New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005).
[113]
Ibid at paragraph 7.46.
[114]
R v Howe [1987] 1 All ER 771.
[115]
Stuart Canadian Criminal Law (3rd
ed Carswell 1995) at 432-3 citing R v Wilcox (1976) 38 CRNS 40, R v
Smith (1977) 40 CRNS 390, R v Bergstrom (1980) 52 CCC (2d) 407 and R
v Mena (1987) 34 CCC (3d) 304.
[116]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Criminal
Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences (Working Paper 29 1982). See
paragraph 3.33 for full text of draft provision.
[117]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Report:
Recodifying Criminal Law (No 30 Volume 1 1986) at 32-33.
[118]
[1967] VR 526. See paragraph 2.33
above.
[120]
The law in New South Wales, on the
other hand, reflects the English position in this respect. R v Abusafiah (1991)
24 NSWLR 531.
[121]
In the Northern Territory, there are
four constituent elements to the defence of duress, namely, a belief that the
person making the threat was in a position to execute the threat; a belief that
there was no alternative; an ordinary person would have taken the same or
similar action; and a requirement that the defendant report the threat to a
police officer as soon as was reasonably practicable. Section 40 Criminal
Code of the Northern Territory of Australia.
[122]
See paragraph 3.45 below.
[123]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Defences
to Homicide: Final Report (2004) at paragraph 3.161.
[124]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Duress,
Necessity and Coercion (No 9 1980) at paragraph 4.19.
[125]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Defences
to Homicide: Final Report (2004) at paragraph 3.158.
[126]
Ibid at paragraph 3.163.
[127]
R v Raroa [1987] 2 NZLR 486;
Section 24 Crimes Act 1961.
[128]
American Law Institute Commentary
on Tentative Draft No. 10 of the Model Penal Code (1960) 7.
[130]
The Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Legislating the Criminal Code: Offences against the
Person and General Principles (No 218 1993) at paragraph 29.14.
[131]
Ibid.
[132]
Smith “Duress and Steadfastness: In
Pursuit of the Unintelligible” [1999] Crim LR 363.
[133]
Horder “Occupying the moral high
ground? The Law Commission on duress” [1994] Crim LR 334 at 342.
[134]
Smith “Must Heroes Behave
Heroically?" [1989] Crim LR 622 at 626.
[135]
See the discussion of the
application of duress to homicide in Chapter 3 below.
[136] R v Bowen
[1986] 2 Cr App Rep 157.
[137]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993) paragraphs 29.11-29.14.
[138]
Law Commission of England and Wales A
New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005) at paragraph 7.2.
[139]
Yeo Compulsion in the Criminal
Law (The Law Book Company Ltd 1990) at 227.
[140]
Elliot “Necessity, Duress and Self
Defence” [1989] Crim. Law Rev 611 at 614.
[141]
See Law Reform Commission Consultation
Paper on Homicide: The Plea of Provocation (LRC CP 27-2003), discussing the
subjective nature of the test in current Irish law.
[142]
[1975] 1 All ER 8.
[143]
B (a minor) v DPP [2000] 2 AC 428; R v K [2002] 1 Cr App Rep 13. See McAuley "Beckford
and the Criminal Law Defences" (1990) 41 Northern Ireland Legal
Quarterly 158.
[144]
McAuley "Beckford and
the Criminal Law Defences" (1990) 41 NILQ 158.
[145]
Horder “Occupying the moral high
ground? The Law Commission on Duress” [1994] Crim LR 334 at 341.
[146]
Elliot “Necessity, Duress and Self
Defence” [1989] Crim LR 611 at 615.
[148]
Yeo Compulsion in the Criminal
Law (The Law Book Company 1990) at 230.
[149]
Fisse Howard’s Criminal Law (5th
ed The Law Book Company 1990) at 552-3.
[150]
[1934] IR 518, 526. See paragraph 2.03
above.
[151]
(1746) 18 St Tr 391.
[152]
Ibid.
[153]
[1971] 2 QB 202.
The circumstances in Hudson and Taylor are comparable to those in
The People (DPP) v Amanda McNamara, Circuit Criminal Court, 7 February
2006, Irish Times, 8 February 2006. The defendant had given a statement to the
Garda Síochána implicating a person, Liam Keane, in a death. At the subsequent
murder trial of Liam Keane, the defendant was called as a prosecution witness
but contradicted her earlier statement saying that she no longer could stand
over its contents as she no longer remembered the events surrounding the
murder, as she had been so high on drink and drugs at the time: arising from
this and similar actions by other witnesses, the murder trial collapsed. The
defendant was then charged with perjury. She pleaded guilty to the charge, but
at sentencing her counsel was reported to have argued that she had been subject
to a “campaign of fear and intimidation.” Duress was not raised in this
case by way of defence, but it is notable that it was argued in mitigation at
the sentencing stage. At the time of writing, sentencing of the defendant
is still awaited, pending hearings involving 2 other perjury cases arising from
the collapsed trial.
[154]
[1999] Crim LR 570.
[155]
Ibid, 570.
[156]
[2005] 4 All ER 685. See paragraph
2.15 above.
[157]
Ibid, 698.
[158]
Ryan & Ryan “Resolving the
Duress Dilemma: Guidance from the House of Lords” (2005) 56 NILQ 421 at 427.
[159]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Report on Defences of General Application (No 83 1977) at paragraph
2.46.
[160]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Codification of the Criminal Law (No 143 1986) at paragraph 13.15 to
13.24. Draft Criminal Code Bill 1985 clause 45.
[161]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Codification of the Criminal Law (No 143 1986) at paragraph 13.15 to
13.24. Draft Criminal Code Bill 1985 clause 45. See clause
1(3) of the draft Bill.
[162]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Codification of the Criminal Law (No 143 1986) at paragraph
13.18.
[163]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: A Criminal Code for England and Wales Volume 1: Report and Draft Criminal
Code Bill and Volume 2: Commentary on Draft Criminal Code Bill (No
177 1989).
[164] Law Commission of
England and Wales Criminal Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences
against the Person and General Principles (No 218 1993).
[165]
[1967] SCR 114.
[166]
See Stuart Canadian Criminal Law (3rd
ed Carswell 1995) at 397.
[168]
[2001] 1 SCR 687.
[169]
Ibid at paragraph 53.
[170]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Criminal
Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences (Working Paper 29 1982) at
84-91.
[171]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Report:
Recodifying Criminal Law (No 30 Volume 1 1986) at 33.
[172]
R v Williamson [1972] 2 NSWLR
281.
[173]
[1967] VR 526, discussed at
paragraphs 2.33 and 2.83 above.
[174]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Duress
Necessity and Coercion (No 9 1980) at paragraph 4.19.
[175]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Defences
to Homicide: Final Report (2004) at Recommendation 14.
[176]
[2001] 1 SCR 687. See
paragraph 2.118 above.
[177]
[1967] NZLR 421.
[178]
[1968] NZLR 1070.
[179] Orchard “The
Defence of Compulsion” (1980) 9 New Zealand Universities Law Review 105 at 115.
[180]
[1981] 2 NZLR 64.
[181]
[2001] 1 SCR 687.
[182]
American Law Institute Model Penal
Code 1962 section 2.09.
[183]
Orchard “The Defence of Compulsion”
(1980) 9 New Zealand Universities Law Review 105 at 115; Stuart Canadian
Criminal Law (3rd ed Carswell 1995) at 397.
[184]
[1999] Crim LR 570
[185]
[2001] 1 SCR 687.
[186]
[1999] Crim LR 570.
[187]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Duress,
Necessity and Coercion (No 9 1980) at paragraph 4.19.
[188]
[1934] IR 518. See paragraph 2.03
above.
[189]
[2005] 4 All ER 685. See paragraphs
2.15-2.17 above.
[190]
Ibid, 699.
[191]
Ibid, 702.
[192]
Ibid, 703. It is also worth
noting that in Baroness Hale’s judgment, she expressed concern about how this
limitation might impact on victims of domestic crime and noted that this
limitation on the defence is not aimed at battered wives, or those in close
personal or family relationships with their duressors. However, she said
that the other restrictions on the defence are more than adequate to keep it
within bounds in such cases. Ibid, 715.
[193]
[1977] NI 20.
[194]
[1983] NI 361.
[195]
[1987] 3 All ER 103.
[197]
(1988) 86 Cr App Rep 47.
[198]
Ibid.
[199] Law Commission of
England and Wales Criminal Law: Report on Defences of General Application (No
83 1977).
[200]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993) at paragraph 29.15.
[201]
Law Commission of England and Wales A
New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005).
[202]
[2005] 4 All ER 685. See paragraph
2.15 above.
[203]
Law Commission of England and Wales A
New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005) at paragraph 7.55.
[204]
Section 17 Canadian Criminal Code RS
1985 c. C-46; s. 17 RS 1985, c 27 (1st Supp) s. 40.
[205]
[1983] NI 361. See paragraph
2.139 above.
[206]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Criminal
Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences (Working Paper 29 1982) at
84-91.
[207]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Report:
Recodifying Criminal Law Volume 1 (No 30 1986) at 32-33.
[208]
[1967] VR 526, discussed at
paragraphs 2.33 and 2.83 above.
[209]
O’Connor and Fairall Criminal
Defences (3rd ed Butterworths 1996) at 160.
[210]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Duress
Necessity and Coercion (No 9 1980) at paragraph 4.19.
[211]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Defences
to Homicide: Final Report (2004) at paragraph 3.157 Recommendation 15;
section 10.2(3) Criminal Code Act 1995 (Cth); section 40(3) Criminal
Code 2002 (ACT).
[212]
[1968] NZLR 1070.
[213]
See paragraphs 2.62-2.106 above.
[214]
Elliot “Necessity, Duress and Self
Defence” [1989] Crim LR 611 at 615.
[215]
Yeo Compulsion in the Criminal
Law (The Law Book Company 1990) at 174.
[216]
Ibid.
[217]
The benefit of clergy was originally
a provision by which clergymen could claim that they were outside the
jurisdiction of the secular courts and be tried instead under canon law.
[218]
Coughlin “Excusing Women” (1994) Cal
L Rev 1.
[219]
[1981] IR 412.
[220]
[1977] IR 360.
[221]
Report of the Criminal Law
Commissioner (1845) Parl Pa xxiv 114.
[222]
Avory Committee Report on the
Responsibility of the Wife for Crimes Committed under the Coercion of the
Husband (1922) Cmd 1677.
[223]
Williams Criminal Law: The
General Part (2nd ed Stevens and Sons Ltd 1961) at 764-768.
[224]
(1996) 1 Cr App R 116.
[225]
[1982] Crim LR 507.
[226]
Stephen A History of the Criminal
Law of England (Macmillan 1883) Vol II at 106.
[227]
Williams Criminal Law: The
General Part (2nd ed Stevens and Sons Ltd 1961) at 765.
[228]
[1988] Crim LR 42.
[229]
R v Connelly (1829) 2 Lew
229, 168 ER 1137.
[230]
The Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Report on Defences of General Application (No 83
1977).
[231]
Smith and Hogan Criminal Law (11th
ed Butterworths 2005) at 242.
[232]
Section 18 Canadian Criminal Code R.S., c C-34, s 18;
1980-81-82-83, c 125, s 4.
[233]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Criminal
Law: The General Part – Liability and Defences (Working Paper 29 1982).
[234]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Recodifying
Criminal Law (No 30 1986).
[235]
Section 407A Crimes Act 1900.
[236]
Section 336 Crimes Act 1958.
[237]
Pace “Marital Coercion –Anachronism
or Modernism” 1970 Crim LR 82.
[238]
Section 328A Criminal Law
Consolidation Act 1935.
[239]
Crimes Amendment Act (No 2) 1999.
[240]
Boyce and Perkins Cases and
Materials on Criminal Law and Procedure (7th ed Foundation Press 1989) at 670.
[241]
Coughlin “Excusing Women” (1994) Cal
L Rev 1 at 29.
[242]
R v Oakes [1995] 2 NZLR 673;
R v O'Brien [2003] NSWCCA 121; R. v TLC [2004] ABPC 79.
[243]
Coughlin “Excusing Women” (1994) Cal
L Rev 1 at 50.
[244]
Boyce and Perkins Cases and
Materials on Criminal Law and Procedure (7th ed Foundation Press 1989) at 670.
[245]
Pace “Marital Coercion -Anachronism
or Modernism” 1970 Crim LR 82 at 85.
[246]
Williams Criminal Law: The
General Part (2nd ed Stevens and Sons Ltd 1961) at 765.
[247]
Howard Australian Criminal Law (The
Law Book Company 1965) at 366.
[248]
Court of Criminal Appeal 18 May
1999.
[249]
Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice (36th
ed Sweet and Maxwell 1966) at 21.
[250]
Court of Criminal Appeal 7 May 2003.
[251]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences Against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993) at paragraph 33.1.
[252]
See discussion on application of the
defence of duress to homicide in Chapter 3.
[253]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences Against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993) at paragraph 33.10.
[256]
[2005] 4 All ER 685. See paragraph
2.15 above.
[257]
Ibid, 693.
[258]
Law Commission of England and Wales A
New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005).
[259]
[1934] IR 518. See paragraph 2.03 above.
[260] Ibid,
524. As the discussion at paragraph 2.23 above indicated, the Court
in Whelan used the word ‘justification’ interchangeably with ‘excuse’
and the Commission considers that the word excuse is preferable in this
context.
[261]
See, for example, R v
Smyth [1963] VR 737, DPP for Northern Ireland v Lynch [1975] AC 653, R v Harding [1976] VR
129, R v Howe [1987] 1 All ER 771.
[262]
See judgment of Rose LJ
in R v Abdul-Hussain & Others [1999] Crim LR 570 which referred with
approval to the dicta of Kennedy LJ in R v Pommell (1995) 2 Cr App Rep 607.
[264]
1 Hale PC 51.
[265]
Blackstone Commentaries
IV 30.
[266]
Smith and Hogan Criminal
Law (10th ed Butterworths 2002) at 255; McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000) at 831-834.
[267]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000) at 831.
[268]
(1969) 53 Cr App Rep 569.
[270]
Ibid, 681.
[273]
(1884) 14 QBD 273.
[274]
See paragraph 4.11 below.
[275]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences Against the
Person and General Principles (No 122 1992) at paragraph 18.15.
[276]
R v Howe [1987] AC 417, 443-444.
[277]
[1992] 2 AC 412.
[278]
Hale Pleas of the Crown
at 49-50 and 56-8.
[279]
Ibid at 49.
[280]
Williams Criminal Law: The
General Part (2nd ed Stevens and Sons Ltd 1961) at 762.
[281]
In Oldcastle’s Case the
defence was successfully pleaded in relation to a charge of treason for
supplying food to Sir John Oldcastle and his rebels. (It is notable,
however, that Hale, in his commentary on this case, questions whether the
defence would have been successful if the accused had actually taken part in
the rebellion (1419) 1 Hale PC 50, 1 East PC 70). Duress was also left to
the jury in R v Mc Growther ((1746) 168 ER 8) where the charge was one
of treason for participating in the rebellion of 1745, although the defendant
was ultimately convicted. Similar rulings followed in R v Stratton (1779)
21 How St Tr 1045 and R v Crutchley (1831) 5 C&P 133, both cases
involving treason.
[282]
(1946) 10 JCL 182.
[283]
(1660) 5 How St Tr 1146.
[284]
In R v Steane, a case
involving a statutory form of treason, the Court appeared willing to entertain
duress as a defence but decided the case on other grounds. While Lord
Goddard stated obiter that the defence of duress is not applicable to
treason, this is now widely regarded as bad law. It may be surmised,
therefore, that the defence remains open to many forms of treason, save those
variants of the offence of a particularly grave or immoral character. (R v
Steane [1947] 1 KB 997).
[285]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Codification of the Criminal Law: General Principles Defences of
General Application (No 55 1974).
[286]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law Report on Defences of General Application (No 83
1977).
[287]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: A Criminal Code for England and Wales Volume 1: Report
and Draft Criminal Code Bill and Volume 2: Commentary on Draft Criminal
Code Bill (No 177 1989).
[288]
[1987] AC 417. See paragraph 3.13
above.
[289]
Clause 42(2) Draft Criminal
Code Bill. However, the Commission placed this aspect of the clause
in square brackets as a sign that a question mark remained over this
issue.
[290]
See paragraph 3.15 above.
[291] Law
Commission of England and Wales Criminal Law: Legislating the Criminal Code
Offences Against the Person and General Principles (No 218 1993) at
paragraph 30.11.
[292]
Ibid at paragraph
18.16.
[293]
Ibid at paragraph
30.11.
[294]
See paragraphs 2.62-2.106
above.
[295]
In relation to burden of
proof, see paragraph 2.182-2.192 above.
[296]
Law Commission of England and
Wales A New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005).
[297]
Law Commission of England and
Wales A New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005) at
paragraph 7.26 et seq. The Law Commission notes that a partial defence
may either reduce “first degree murder” to “second degree murder” or else
reduce “first degree murder” and “second degree murder” to manslaughter.
[298]
Ibid at paragraph 7.72.
[299]
RS 1985 c C-46; s17 RS 1985, c
27 (1st Supp) s40.
[300]
Stuart Canadian Criminal
Law (3rd ed Carswell 1995) at 427-8.
[301]
Section 17 Canadian Criminal
Code RS 1985 c C-46; s17 RS 1985, c 27 (1st Supp) s40.
[302]
[1967] SCR 114.
[303]
(1976) 30 CCC (2d) 417.
[304]
Common law defences are
preserved by subsection 7(3) of the Criminal Code.
[305]
Stuart Canadian Criminal
Law (3rd ed Carswell 1995) at 435.
[306]
Law Reform Commission of
Canada Criminal Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences (Working
Paper 29 1982) at 84-91.
[307]
See paragraphs 2.107-2.136
above.
[308]
Law Reform Commission of
Canada Criminal Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences (Working
Paper 29 1982) at 87.
[309]
Law Reform Commission of
Canada Report: Recodifying Criminal Law Volume 1 (No 30 1986) at 32-33.
[310]
Ibid at 32.
[311]
Queensland, Western Australia,
Tasmania, Northern Territory and Australian Capital Territory.
[312]
[1967] VR 526. See
paragraph 2.19 above.
[313]
R v McConnell [1977] 1
NSWLR 714; R v McCafferty [1974] 1 NSWLR 89.
[314]
R v Derrington and McGauley
[1980] VR 353.
[315]
R v Brown and Morely
(1968) SASR 467.
[316]
Criminal Code 1899
(Qd); Criminal Code 1913 (WA).
[317]
This section is mirrored
exactly in section 31 Criminal Code (WA) and section 31 Criminal Code (Qd).
[318]
Section 20(1) Criminal Code
Act 1924.
[319]
“The excuse referred to in
subsection (1) does not extend to … a person who has rendered himself liable to
have such a threat made to him by having entered into an association or
conspiracy that has as any of its objects the doing of a wrongful act”
Section 40(2) Criminal Code of the Northern Territory of Australia.
[320]
“When a person who has
unlawfully killed another under circumstances that, but for this subsection,
would have constituted murder, did the act or made the omission that caused
death because of coercion of such a nature that it would have caused a
reasonable person similarly circumstanced to have acted in the same or a
similar way, he is excused from criminal responsibility for murder and is
guilty of manslaughter only.” Section 41 Criminal Code of the Northern
Territory of Australia.
[321]
Section 10.2 Criminal Code
Act 1995 (Commonwealth of Australia). See also Section 40 Criminal
Code 2002 (ACT).
[322] South
Australia Criminal Law and Penal Methods Committee The Substantive Criminal
Law (No 4 1977) at paragraph 12.5.
[323]
Ibid.
[324] Victorian
Law Reform Commission Duress, Necessity and Coercion (No 5 1978) at
paragraph 2.67.
[325]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law Report on Defences of General Application (No 83 1977).
See paragraph 3.20-3.31 above.
[326]
Victorian Law Reform
Commission Duress, Necessity and Coercion (No 9 1980) at paragraph 4.19.
[327]
Ibid.
[330]
Ibid at paragraphs
2.12-2.15.
[331]
Ibid at paragraph 2.17.
[332]
Ibid at paragraph 2.19.
[333]
Victorian Law Reform
Commission Homicide (No 40 1991) at paragraph 244 Recommendation 31.
[334] Victorian
Law Reform Commission Defences to Homicide: Final Report (2004).
[335]
See paragraph 4.65 below.
[336]
Section 24 Crimes Act 1961.
[337]
(1976) 30 CCC (2d) 417.
[338]
[1993] 2 NZLR 424.
[340]
Perkins and Boyce Criminal
Law (3rd ed Foundation 1982) at 1054-1065.
[341]
American Law Institute Model
Penal Code 1962 section 2.09.
[342]
Reed, “The Need for a New
Anglo-American Approach to Duress” (1997) 61 Journal of Criminal Law 209
at 216.
[343]
S v Goliath (1972) 3 SA
1.
[344]
See paragraph 4.85 below.
[345]
(1947) 2 SA 828, 837. See also
S v Bradbury (1967) 1 SA 387.
[346]
(1972) 3 SA 1.
[347]
Ogilvie Thompson CJ, Jansen JA
and Trollip JA concurring; Wessels JA dissenting.
[348]
(1972) 3 SA 1.
[349]
(1982) 3 SA 772.
[350]
R v Hasan [2005] 4 All ER 685, 694, per Lord
Bingham. See paragraph 2.15 above.
[351]
Milgate, "Duress and the
Criminal Law: Another About Turn by the House of Lords" (1988) 47 CLJ 61
at 63.
[352]
[1977] AC 755, 771.
[353]
Sornarajah “Duress and Murder
in Commonwealth Criminal Law” (1981) 30 International and Comparative Law
Quarterly 660.
[354]
Stuart Canadian Criminal
Law (3rd Ed Carswell 1995) at 436.
[355]
Milgate, H.P., "Duress
and the Criminal Law: Another About Turn by the House of Lords" (1988) 47
CLJ 61 at 63.
[356]
1 Hale PC 51; Blackstone Commentaries IV 30.
[357]
Law Commission Criminal
Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences Against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993) at paragraph 30.11.
[358]
Milgate "Duress and the
Criminal Law: Another About Turn by the House of Lords" (1988) 47 CLJ 61
at 67; Gearty “Howe to be a Hero” [1987] CLJ 203.
[359]
Horder “Autonomy, Provocation and
Duress” [1992] Crim LR 706 at 709.
[360]
Hall General Principles of the
Criminal Law (2nd ed Bobbs-Merrill 1960) at 444-448; Stephen A
History of the Criminal law of England (Macmillan 1883) Vol I at 107.
[361]
Walters “Murder under duress and
judicial decision making in the House of Lords” (1988) 8 Legal Studies
61 at 69.
[363]
Per Lord Lane.
[364]
[1975] AC 675, 687-688.
[366]
Milgate H.P. "Duress and the
Criminal Law: Another About Turn by the House of Lords" (1988) 47 CLJ 61
at 72.
[367]
R v Howe [1987] 1 All ER 771.
[368]
Milgate H.P. "Duress and the
Criminal Law: Another About Turn by the House of Lords" (1988) 47 CLJ 61
at 71.
[369]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Criminal
Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences (Working Paper No 29 1982)
at 91-96.
[370]
[1987] All ER 771, 785.
[371]
Stephen A History of the Criminal
law of England (Macmillan 1883) Vol II at 108.
[372]
[2005] 4 All ER 685, 696. See
paragraph 2.15 above.
[373]
[1975] AC 653, 686. See Ryan &
Ryan “Resolving the Duress Dilemma: Guidance from the House of Lords” (2005) 56
NILQ 421 at 430.
[374]
Law Commission of England and Wales A
New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005). See paragraph 3.27
above for recommendations.
[375] Fletcher “The
Individualisation of Excusing Conditions” (1974) 47 S Cal LR 1269 at 1308.
[376]
Law Commission of England and Wales A
New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (No 177 2005).
[377]
Ibid at paragraph 7.62.
[378]
Ashworth Principles of Criminal
Law (4th ed Oxford University Press 2003) at 230 and 280.
[379]
[1987] All ER 771.
[380]
[1975] AC 653, 670.
[381] [1987] All ER
771, 790.
[382]
See Law Reform Commission Consultation
Paper on Homicide: The Plea of Provocation (LRC CP 27-2003).
[383]
Horder “Autonomy, Provocation and
Duress” [1992] Crim LR 706 at 709.
[384]
Further, in R v Howe, Lord
Hailsham, in rejecting the use of duress as a partial defence, argued that
provocation can be distinguished from duress in that provocation involves an
emotional loss of self control while duress involves a conscious decision which
can be coolly undertaken (R v Howe [1987] All ER 771, 782).
[385]
Law Commission Criminal Law:
Legislating the Criminal Code Offences Against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993) at paragraph 30.11.
[386]
See paragraphs 3.20-3.31 above.
[387]
R v Hasan [2005] 4 All ER 685, 695, per
Lord Bingham. See paragraph 2.15 above.
[388]
Victoria Law Reform Commission Defences
to Homicide: Final Report Recommendation 13.
[389]
Sections 10.2 and 10.3 Criminal
Code Act 1995 (Cth); sections 40 and 41 Criminal Code 2002 (ACT).
[390]
See paragraphs 1.08-1.11 above
[391]
Since the defence of
duress of circumstances, as developed by the English courts, concerns
constraints imposed by surrounding circumstances, it can be seen as a form of
necessity.
[392]
See generally Charleton,
McDermott and Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 1075-1085;
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000)
at 779-822 and Smith and Hogan Criminal Law (10th ed
Butterworths 2002) at 266-275.
[393]
See Charleton, McDermott
and Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 1084-1085; McAuley and
McCutcheon Criminal Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000) at
817-822. It has been argued that the circumstances in Attorney General
v X, [1992] ILRM 401, involved a case of necessity. In that case,
the Supreme Court held that a doctor may lawfully perform an
abortion where there is a “real and substantial risk” to the life of the
mother, which includes a risk of suicide. The defence is only open,
however, where there is a need to preserve the life, as opposed to
the health of the
mother. It has been noted that although these cases are usually treated
as examples of necessity, they do not involve a requirement that the defendant
chose the lesser of two evils: See McAuley and McCutcheon at 821.
[394]
As amended by section 21
of the Non Fatal Offences Against the Person Act 1997
[395]
(1552) 1 Plowd 1, 18.
[396]
Ibid. See argument
of Sergeant Pollard, which appears to have been accepted by the Court.
[397]
Williams Criminal
Law: The General Part (2nd ed Stevens and Sons Ltd 1961) at 724.
[398]
Re F [1990] 2 AC 1.
[399]
R v Bournewood
Community and Mental Health NHS Trust [1999] 1 AC 458.
[400]
[1990] 2 AC 1, 74 A-C.
[401]
[1999] 1 AC 458, 488. The Bournewood
case and Re F were applied in the more recent conjoined twins case, Re
A (Children) [2000] 4 All ER 961. See paragraph
4.22 below.
[402]
See HL v The United Kingdom
45508/99 European Court of Human Rights 5 October 2004.
[404]
Gardner “Direct Action and the
Defence of Necessity” [2005] Crim LR 371.
[405]
R v Shayler [2003] 1 AC 247, 266.
[406]
[2005]
EWCA Crim 1415, discussed below at paragraph 4.27.
[407]
(1884) 14 QBD 273.
[408]
It has been suggested that the
fact that the death sentence was commuted to such a short sentence was an acknowledgment
that although Dudley and Stephens had broken the law, they had done so under
conditions of overwhelming necessity.
[409]
Williams Criminal Law: The
General Part (2nd ed Stevens and Sons Ltd 1961) at 744.
[410]
26 Fed Cas 360 (1842).
[411]
R v Dudley and Stephens (1884)
14 QBD 273, 279.
[412]
Glazebrook “The Necessity Plea
in English Law” (1972) 30 CLJ 87 at 114.
[413]
See paragraphs 4.23 and
4.104-4.106.
[414]
Howard Australian Criminal
Law (The Law Book Company 1965).
[415]
Williams Criminal Law: The
General Part (2nd ed Stevens and Sons Ltd 1961) at 744.
[416]
Bennun “Necessity- yet another
analysis?” (1986) 21 Irish Jurist 186 at 198.
[417]
[1987] 1 All ER 771 discussed at paragraphs
3.13-3.16.
[418]
Smith and Hogan Criminal
Law (8th ed Butterworths 1996) at 252.
[419]
[1987] 1 All ER 771. See paragraph
3.13 above.
[421]
[1978] AC 653. See
paragraphs 3.10-3.12 above.
[422]
R v Howe [1987] 1 All ER 771, 780.
[423]
(1972) (3) SALR 465.
[425]
S v Goliath (1972) (3)
SALR 465, 480.
[426]
Ibid.
[427]
R v Howe [1987] 1 All ER 771, 779.
[429]
(1884) 14 QBD 273.
[431]
These circumstances were
described by an army corporal at the coroner’s inquest in October 1987 into the
sinking of The Herald of Free Enterprise. See paragraphs 4.14 above and
4.104-4.106 below.
[432]
(1884) 14 QBD 273.
[434]
Ibid.
[437]
See Law Commission of England
and Wales Criminal Law: Report on Defences of General Application (No 83
1977) at paragraphs 4.15- 4.33.
[438] Watson “A
necessary defence” (1999) The Criminal Lawyer No. 90.
[439]
R v Morgenthaler (1975)
53 DLR (3d) 161.
[440]
Ibid, per Dickson
J.
[441]
Williams Textbook on
Criminal Law (Stevens and Sons Ltd 1978) at 556.
[442]
London Borough of Southwark
v Williams [1971] 2 All ER 175.
[443]
R v Pommell (1995) 2 Cr
App Rep 300.
[444]
R v Willer (1986) 83 Cr
App Rep 225, R v Conway [1989] QB 290, R v Martin [1989] 1 All ER 652.
[445]
(1986) 83 Cr App Rep 225.
[446]
Ibid, 227.
Emphasis added.
[448]
R v Conway [1989] QB 290 Woolf LJ citing Smith and
Hogan Criminal Law (6th ed Butterworths 1988) at 255.
[449]
[1987] 1 All ER 771, 777. See
paragraph 3.13 above.
[450]
[1982] 1 All ER 801. See paragraphs
2.65-2.66 and 2.75 above.
[451]
Ibid, 805-806.
[452]
Elliot “Necessity, Duress and
Self Defence” [1989] Crim LR 611.
[453]
Ibid.
[457]
Norrie Crime, Reason and
History (Butterworths 1993) 163.
[459]
Elliot “Necessity, Duress and
Self Defence” [1989] Crim LR 611 at 614.
[460]
Slapper “Public Policy under
Duress” 145 (1995) New Law Journal 1063.
[461] [1994] Crim
LR 582
[462]
(1995) 2 Cr App Rep 607, 615.
[463]
Ibid, 615 per Kennedy
J quoting Smith Case and Comment on DPP v Bell [1992] Crim LR 176.
[464]
[1999] Crim LR 570.
[467]
Ibid at paragraph [35].
[469]
(1995) 2 Cr App Rep 607, 615.
[470]
[1999] Crim LR 570.
[472]
[2001] 1 WLR 2206, 2226.
[473]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000) at 822.
[474]
Smith “Duress and
Steadfastness: In Pursuit of the Unintelligible” [1999] Crim LR 363 at 367.
[475]
Section 18(3) of the Irish Non
Fatal Offences Against the Person Act 1997, which deals with the
justifiable use of force against a criminal act, provides that such an act will
be deemed to have occurred even where the actor would have a defence on grounds
of “duress, whether by threats or of circumstances.” It has been
tentatively suggested that this would seem to indicate legislative acceptance
of the defence of duress of circumstances, but such a defence has not been
recognised by the Irish courts, and it remains unclear as to whether this
constitutes legislative acceptance of the defence.
[476]
Watson “A Necessary Defence”
(1999) The Criminal Lawyer No 90.
[477]
Ibid, as noted by
Murnaghan J. in AG v Whelan (1934) IR 518. See paragraph 3.02
above.
[478]
Smith and Hogan Criminal
Law (10th ed Butterworths 2002).
[479]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Codification of the Criminal Law: General Principles Defences of
General Application (Working Paper No 55 1974).
[480]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Report on Defences of General Application (No 83
1977).
[481]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Codification of the Criminal Law: General Principles Defences of
General Application (Working Paper No 55 1974) at paragraph 38.
[482]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Report on Defences of General Application (No 83
1977).
[483]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Report on Defences of General Application (No 83
1977) at paragraph 4.30.
[484]
As noted by Williams “Defences
of General Application: Necessity” [1978] Crim LR 128.
[485]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Codification of the Criminal Law A Report to the Law
Commission (No 143 1985).
[486]
Williams Textbook of
Criminal Law (2nd ed Stevens and Sons Ltd 1983) at 602.
[487]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Codification of the Criminal Law A Report to the Law
Commission (No 143 1985) at paragraph 13.25.
[488]
Law Commission of England and
Wales Criminal Law: Codification of the Criminal Law A Report to the Law
Commission (No 143 1985) at 120.
[489]
Ibid. Clause 46 Draft
Criminal Code Bill.
[490]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: A Criminal Code for England and Wales Volume 1: Report and Draft Criminal
Code Bill and Volume 2: Commentary on Draft Criminal Code Bill (No
177 1989).
[491]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: A Criminal Code for England and Wales Volume 1: Report and Draft Criminal
Code Bill and Volume 2: Commentary on Draft Criminal Code Bill (No
177 1989) at paragraph 12.20.
[492]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993).
[493]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: A Criminal Code for England and Wales Volume 1: Report and Draft Criminal
Code Bill Clause 26.
[494]
(1884) 14 QBD 273.
[495]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993) at paragraph 35.11.
[496]
Ibid at paragraph 35.3.
[497]
Ibid at paragraph 35.4.
[498]
Ibid at paragraph 35.5.
[499]
Re F [1990] 2 AC 1.
[500]
[1969] VR 667.
[501]
[1981] VR 433.
[502]
[1981] VR 433, 448.
[503]
Section 25 Criminal Code Act
Compilation Act 1913.
[504]
Section 25 Criminal Code Act 1899.
[505]
Section 33 Criminal Code Act 1983.
[506]
Sections 10.2 and 10.3 Criminal
Code Act 1995 (Cth).
[507]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Duress,
Necessity and Coercion (Working Paper 5 1978).
[508]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Duress,
Necessity and Coercion (No 9 1980).
[509]
Ibid at paragraph 3.28.
[510]
Ibid at paragraph 3.47.
[511]
Ibid at paragraph 4.19.
[512]
(1884) 14 QBD 273.
[513]
Ibid at paragraph 4.04.
[514]
See paragraph 4.86 below.
[515]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Duress,
Necessity and Coercion (No 9 1980) at paragraph 4.19.
[516]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Homicide
(No 40 1991).
[517]
(1884) 14 QBD 273.
[518]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Defences
to Homicide: Final Report (2004).
[519]
Sections 10.2 and 10.3 of the Criminal
Code Act 1995.
[520]
Victorian Law Reform Commission Defences
to Homicide: Final Report (2004) Recommendation 13.
[521]
Ibid at Recommendation 16.
[522]
[1984] 2 SCR 232.
[523]
Ibid, 406.
[524]
Ibid.
[525] (1975) 53 DLR
(3d) 161.
[526]
(2001) 150 CCC (3d) 129.
[527]
R v Latimer (2001) 150 CCC
(3d) 129, 148.
[528]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Criminal
Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences (Working Paper No 29 1982)
at 91-96.
[529]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Criminal
Law: The General Part - Liability and Defences (Working Paper No 29 1982)
at 94.
[530]
(1884) 14 QBD 273.
[531]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Recodifying
Criminal Law Volume 1 (No 30 1987) at 33-34.
[532]
Law Reform Commission of Canada Recodifying
Criminal Law Volume 1 (No 30 1987) at 33-34.
[533]
[1984] 2 SCR 232.
[534]
This was discussed in the context of
homicide above at paragraph 3.60
and in the context of the nature of the threats at paragraph 2.38.
[535]
Burchell and Hunt South African
Criminal Law and Procedure Volume 1: General Principles of Criminal Law (3rd
ed Juta 1997) at 89.
[536]
Section 34 German Federal Penal
Code.
[537]
Section 35 German Federal Penal
Code.
[538]
Williams “The Theory of Excuses”
[1982] Crim LR 732; Robinson “Criminal Law Defences: A Systematic Analysis” 82
Col L Rev (1982) 199.
[539]
Clarkson “Necessary Action: A New
Defence” [2004] Crim LR 13.
[540]
Section 34 German Federal Penal
Code.
[541]
Bernsmann “Private Self-defence and
Necessity in German Penal law and in the Penal law Proposal- some remarks” 1996
30 Is LR 1-2 171 at 183.
[542]
(1884) 14 QBD 273.
[543]
Section 35 German Federal Penal
Code.
[544]
Bernsmann “Private Self-defence and
Necessity in German Penal Law and in the Penal Law Proposal- Some Remarks”
(1996) 30 Is LR 1-2 171 at 185.
[545] Bernsmann
“Private Self-defence and Necessity in German Penal Law and in the Penal Law
Proposal- Some Remarks” (1996) 30 Is LR 1-2 171 at 185.
[546]
Ibid at 187.
[547]
See McAuley, ‘The Theory of
Justification and Excuse: Some Italian Lessons’ (1987) 35 AJCL 359.
[548]
See Introduction at paragraph 1 above.
[549]
Section 81.
[550]
Division 10.
[551]
Title 4.
[552]
Scottish Law Commission Draft
Criminal Code for Scotland (2003) at 66.
[553]
American Law Institute Model Penal
Code paragraph 3.02. It is noteworthy that the Scottish High Court
of Justiciary have recently observed in Lord Advocate’s Reference (No. 1 of
2000) (2001) SCCR 296 that “the formulation of the defence of necessity in the
American Law Institute’s Model Penal Code… appeared to suffer from a number of
defects” and that “American codifications of the criminal law were unlikely to
provide a reliable basis for ascertaining Scots law.”
[554]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993).
[555]
Law Commission of England and Wales Criminal
Law: Legislating the Criminal Code Offences against the Person and General
Principles (No 218 1993) at paragraph 35.5.
[556] Walters “Murder
under duress and judicial decision making in the House of Lords” (1988) 8 Legal
Studies 61 at 71.
[557]
[1934] IR 518, 526.
[558]
[1975] AC 653, 680.
[559]
[1987] All ER 771.
[560]
[1984] 2 SCR 232.
[561]
Ibid, 250.
[562]
[2000] 4 All ER 961, 1064.
[563]
S v Bailey (1982) 3 SA 772.
[564]
See paragraph 4.86 above.
[565]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000) at 787.
[566]
See paragraphs 4.15 and 4.23 above.
[567]
Ibid.
[568]
Bennun “Necessity- Yet Another
Analysis?” (1986) Irish Jurist 186 at 198
[569]
Smith and Hogan Criminal Law
(10th ed Butterworths 2002) at 273.
[570]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000) at 825.
[571]
Watson “A Necessary Defence” (1999) The
Criminal Lawyer No. 90.
[572]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000) at 826.
[573]
See paragraph 4.86-4.89 above.
[574]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000) at 786.
[575]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Roundhall Sweet and Maxwell 2000) at 801.