CONSULTATION PAPER
(LRCCP 48-2008 )
IRELAND
Law
Reform Commission
35-39
Shelbourne Road, Ballsbridge, Dublin 4
© Copyright
Law Reform Commission
First Published
ISSN 1393-3140
THE LAW REFORM COMMISSION
Background
The Law Reform Commission is an independent statutory body
whose main aim is to keep the law under review and to make practical proposals
for its reform. It was established on 20 October 1975, pursuant to
section 3 of the Law Reform Commission Act 1975.
The Commission’s Second Programme for Law Reform, prepared
in consultation with the Attorney General, was approved by the Government and
copies were laid before both Houses of the Oireachtas in December 2000.
The Commission also works on matters which are referred to it on occasion by
the Attorney General under the terms of the Act.
To date the Commission has published Reports
containing proposals for reform of the law; eleven Working Papers; Consultation Papers; a number of specialised Papers
for limited circulation; An Examination of the Law of Bail; and Annual Reports in accordance with section 6 of the
1975 Act. A full list of its publications is contained on the
Commission’s website at www.lawreform.ie.
Membership
The Law Reform Commission consists of a President, one
full-time Commissioner and three part-time Commissioners.
The Commissioners at present are:
President: |
The Hon Mrs Justice Catherine McGuinness, former Judge of the Supreme Court |
|
|
Full-time Commissioner: |
Patricia T. Rickard-Clarke, Solicitor |
|
|
Part-time Commissioner: |
Professor Finbarr McAuley |
|
|
Marian Shanley, Solicitor |
|
|
|
Part-time Commissioner: |
Donal O’Donnell, Senior Counsel |
|
|
Secretary/Head of Administration |
John Quirke |
Research Staff
Director of Research: |
Raymond Byrne BCL, LLM, Barrister-at-Law |
|
|
Legal Researchers: |
John P. Byrne BCL, LLM (NUI), Barrister-at-Law |
|
Áine Clancy BCL, LLM (NUI) |
|
Philip Flaherty BCL, LLM (NUI) |
|
|
|
|
|
Margaret Maguire LLB, LLM (NUI) |
|
Jane Mulcahy BCL (Law and German), LLM (NUI) |
|
|
|
Richard McNamara BCL, LLM (NUI) |
|
Charles O’Mahony BA, LLB, LLM (Lond), LLM (NUI) |
|
|
|
|
|
Nicola White LLB, LLM (Dub), Attorney-at-Law (NY) |
Administration Staff
Pearse Rayel |
|
|
|
Executive Officer: |
|
|
|
Legal Information Manager: |
Conor Kennedy BA, H Dip LIS |
|
|
Cataloguer: |
Eithne Boland BA (Hons), HDip Ed, HDip LIS |
|
|
Information Technology Officer: |
Liam Dargan |
|
|
Private Secretary to the President: |
|
|
|
Clerical Officer: |
Ann Browne |
Principal Legal Researcher on this Publication
David Prendergast LLB, LLM (Lond), Barrister-at-Law
Contact Details
Further information can be obtained from:
The
Secretary
The Law Reform
Commission
35-39 Shelbourne
Road Ballsbridge Dublin 4
T: |
+353 1 637 7600 |
F: |
+353 1 637 7601 |
|
|
E: |
info@lawreform.ie |
W: |
www.lawreform.ie |
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS/THE PROJECT
Table of
Legislation
xi
Table of
Cases
xiii
B Introduction
to inchoate offences
D Outline
of this Consultation Paper
C The
rationale of inchoate offences
(1) Retributivism and
harm prevention
D Criminal
law theory engaged by inchoate offences
(2) Subjectivism and
objectivism
(3) The significance
of mens rea for inchoate offences
E Inchoate
liability and secondary liability
F Inchoate
offences in practice
(2) Inchoate offences
in the wide sense
G Codification
of inchoate offences
(1) Categories of
impossible attempts
(2) Irish judicial
comment on impossible attempts
(3) The debate about
impossible attempts
(4) The irrelevance
of impossibility
(1) The relevance of
abandonment to attempt liability
(2) The mens rea of
conspiracy
C The
unlawfulness requirement
D Specific
common law conspiracies
(2) Conspiracy to
corrupt public morals
(3) Other specific
common law conspiracies
(1) Arguments for and
against restricting conspiracy to agreements to commit crimes
(2) The case for
retaining conspiracy to defraud
(3) Developments and
recommendations elsewhere
B The
components of incitement
(1) The actus reus of
incitement
(2) The mens rea of
incitement
(1) A perceived gap
in liability
E Abandonment
of an incitement
CHAPTER 5 provisional
recommendations
(3) The target of a
conspiracy
(5) Withdrawal from a
conspiracy
(3) The target of an
incitement
1967, c. 87 |
Eng |
|
Child Trafficking and Pornography Act 1998 |
1998, No. 22 |
Irl |
Crimes Act 1958 (Vic) |
1958, No. 6231 |
Aus |
Crimes Act 1961 |
1961, No. 43 |
NZ |
Criminal Attempts Act 1981 |
1981, c. 47 |
Eng |
Criminal Code Act 1899 (Qld) |
1899 |
Aus |
Criminal Justice (Theft and Fraud Offences) Act 2001 |
2001, No. 50 |
Irl |
Criminal Justice Act 2006 |
2006, No. 26 |
Irl |
Criminal Law Act 1977 |
1977, c. 45 |
Eng |
Criminal Law Act 1997 |
1997, No. 14 |
Irl |
Explosive Substances Act 1883 |
1883, 46 & 47 Vict. c. 3. |
Eng |
Firearms Act 1925 |
1925, No. 17 |
Irl |
Firearms and Offensive Weapons Act 1990 |
1990, No. 12 |
Irl |
Immigration Act 1971 |
1971, c. 77 |
Eng |
Italian Penal Code |
|
Ita |
Misuse of Drugs Act 1971 |
1971, c. 38 |
Eng |
Non-Fatal Offences Against the Person Act 1997 |
1997, No. 26 |
Irl |
Offences Against the Person Act 1861 |
1861, 24 & 25 Vict. c. 100 |
Eng |
Offences Against the State Act 1939 |
1939, No. 13 |
Irl |
Prohibition of Incitement to Hatred Act 1989 |
1989, No. 19 |
Irl |
Road Traffic Act 1961 |
1961, No. 24 |
Irl |
Serious Crime Act 2007 |
2007, c. 27 |
Eng |
Sexual Offences Act 1967 |
1967, c. 60 |
Eng |
South Australia Criminal Law Consolidation Act 1935 |
|
Aus |
Terrorism Act 2006 |
2006, c. 11 |
Eng |
TABLE OF CASES
Eng |
||
Attorney General (SPUC) v Open Door Counselling Ltd |
[1988] IR 593 |
Irl |
Attorney General for England and Wales v Brandon Book Publishers Ltd |
[1986] IR 597 |
Irl |
Attorney General v Oldridge |
Irl |
|
Attorney General v Richmond |
(1935) 1 Frewen 28 |
Irl |
Attorny v Starling |
(1664) 83 ER 1164 |
Eng |
Board of Trade v Owen |
[1957] AC 602 |
Eng |
Brandenburg v Ohio |
(1969) 395 US 444 |
US |
Cawthorne v HM Advocate |
Sco |
|
Churchill v Walton |
[1967] 2 AC 224 |
Eng |
Connolly v Loughney |
(1953) 87 ILTR 49 |
Irl |
Corway v Independent Newspapers |
Irl |
|
Davey v Lee |
[1967] 2 All ER 423 |
Eng |
de Gortari v Smithwick (No 2) |
Irl |
|
DPP v Armstrong |
[2000] Crim LR 379 |
Eng |
DPP v Carew |
[1981] ILRM 91 |
Irl |
DPP v Nock and Alsford |
[1978] AC 979 |
Eng |
DPP v Shannon |
[1975] AC 717 |
Eng |
DPP v Stonehouse |
[1978] AC 55 |
Eng |
DPP v Withers |
[1975] AC 842 |
Eng |
Ellis v O’Dea and Governor of Portlaoise Prison |
[1991] ILRM 365 |
Irl |
Haughton v Smith |
Eng |
|
Hegarty v Governor of Limerick Prison |
Irl |
|
Hyam v DPP |
Eng |
|
Instan |
[1893] 1 QB 450 |
Eng |
Invicta Plastics Ltd v Clare |
[1976] RTR 251 |
Eng |
Jones v Brooks |
(1968) 52 Cr App R 614 |
Eng |
Kamara v DPP |
[1973] 2 All ER 1242 |
Eng |
Knuller v DPP |
[1973] AC 435 |
Eng |
Kowbel v R |
[1954] SCR 498 |
Can |
Lajoie v R |
[1974] SCR 399 |
Can |
Leigh |
(1775) 1 C & K 28n |
Eng |
Liangsiriprasert v Government of the United States of America |
[1991] 1 AC 225 |
Eng |
Mawji v R |
[1957] AC 526 |
Eng |
McGee v Attorney General |
Irl |
|
Morton v Henderson |
(1956) JC 55 |
Sco |
Mulcahy v R |
(1868) LR 3 HL 306 |
Eng |
Murray v Ireland |
[1991] ILRM 465 |
Irl |
Myles v Sreenan |
Irl |
|
Nernich |
(1915) 24 CCC 256 |
Can |
O'Sullivan v Conroy |
High Court, 31 July 1997 |
Irl |
Parker v State |
113 SE 218 (1922) |
US |
People v Dlugash |
(1977) 363 NE 2d 1155 |
US |
People v Rizzo |
(1927) 158 N.E. 888 |
US |
R v Déry |
[2006] SCC 53 |
Can |
R (O) v Coventry Magistrates’ Court |
[2004] Crim LR 948 |
Eng |
R v Abu Hamza |
Eng |
|
R v Ancio |
(1984) 39 CR (3d) 1 |
Can |
R v Anderson |
[1986] AC 27 |
Eng |
R v Banks |
(1873) 12 Cox CC 393 |
Eng |
R v Barker |
[1924] NZLR 865 |
NZ |
R v Blamires Transport Services Ltd |
[1964] 1 QB 278 |
Eng |
R v Booth |
[1999] Crim LR 144 |
Eng |
R v Boston |
(1923) 33 CLR 386 |
Aus |
R v Brown |
(1889) 24 QBD 357 |
Eng |
R v Button |
[1900] 2 QB 597 |
Eng |
R v Campbell |
[1991] Crim LR 286 |
Eng |
R v Clayton |
(1943) 33 Cr App R 113 |
Eng |
R v Collins |
(1864) 9 Cox CC 497 |
Eng |
R v Cooke |
[1986] AC 909 |
Eng |
R v Coughlan |
(1976) 64 Cr App R 11 |
Eng |
R v Curr |
[1968] 2 QB 944 |
Eng |
R v Daniell |
(1703) 87 ER 856 |
Eng |
R v Darby |
(1982) 148 CLR 668 |
Aus |
R v De Kromme |
(1892) 17 Cox CC 492 |
Eng |
R v Doot |
[1973] 1 All ER 940 |
Eng |
R v Duguid |
(1906) 75 LJKB 470 |
Eng |
R v Dungey |
(1980) 51 CCC (2d) 86 |
Can |
R v Eagleton |
[1845-60] All ER 363 |
Eng |
R v El-Faisal |
Eng |
|
R v Evans |
[1986] Crim LR 470 |
Eng |
R v Fitzmaurice |
Eng |
|
R v Frankland |
(1985) 23 CCC (3d) 385 |
Can |
R v Geddes |
[1996] Crim LR 894 |
Eng |
R v Gibbins and Proctor |
(1918) 13 Cr App R 134 |
Eng |
R v Goldman |
[2001] Crim LR 822 |
Eng |
R v Goodman |
(1832) 22 UCCP 338 |
Can |
R v Gralewicz |
[1980] 2 SCR 493 |
Can |
R v Gullefer |
[1990] 3 All ER 882 |
Eng |
R v Hancock and Shankland |
Eng |
|
R v Higgins |
(1801) 2 East 5 |
Eng |
R v Howes |
(1971) 2 SASR 293 |
Aus |
R v James and Ashford |
(1985) 82 Cr App R 226 |
Eng |
R v Jones |
(1832) 110 ER 485 |
Eng |
R v Journeymen Tailors |
(1721) 8 Mod 10 |
Eng |
R v Khan |
[1990] 2 All ER 783 |
Eng |
R v Kosh |
(1965) 44 CR 185 |
Can |
R v Lankford |
[1959] Crim LR 209 |
Eng |
R v Maunder |
(1966) 1 CCC 328 |
Can |
R v McDonough |
(1962) 47 Cr App R 37 |
Eng |
R v McPhillips |
(1990) 6 BNIL |
NI |
R v Mohan |
[1976] QB 1 |
Eng |
R v Moloney |
Eng |
|
R v Most |
(1881) 7 QBD 244 |
Eng |
R v Murphy |
(1837) 173 ER 502 |
Eng |
R v Nedrick |
Eng |
|
R v O’Brien |
[1954] SCR 666 |
Can |
R v Osborn |
(1919) 84 JP 63 |
Eng |
R v Page |
[1933] ALR 374 |
Aus |
R v Parnell |
(1881) 14 Cox 508 |
Irl |
R v Peck |
(1839) 9 A and E 686 |
Eng |
R v Pigg |
[1982] 1 WLR 762 |
Eng |
R v Plummer |
[1902] 2 KB 339 |
Eng |
R v Porter |
[1980] NI 18 |
NI |
R v Rankin |
(1848) 7 St Tr (NS) 712 |
Eng |
R v Ransford |
(1874) 13 Cox CC 9 |
Eng |
R v Ring |
(1892) 17 Cox CC 491 |
Eng |
R v Robinson |
(1746) 1 Leach 37 |
Eng |
R v Saik |
Eng |
|
R v Schofield |
(1784) Cald 397 |
Eng |
R v Shivpuri |
Eng |
|
R v Sirat |
(1985) 83 Cr App R 41 |
Eng |
R v Taafe |
[1983] 1 WLR 627 |
Eng |
R v Taylor |
(1859) 1 F & F 511 |
Eng |
R v Tosti |
[1997] Crim LR 746 |
Eng |
R v Tyrrell |
[1894] 1 QB 710 |
Eng |
R v Whitechurch |
(1890) 24 QBD 420 |
Eng |
R v Whitehouse |
(1852) 6 Cox CC 38 |
Eng |
R v Whitehouse |
Eng |
|
R v Whybrow |
[1951] 35 Cr App R 141 |
Eng |
R v Whyte |
[1910] 2 KB 124 |
Eng |
R v Woolin |
Eng |
|
R(Lanktree) v M’Carthy |
(1902-1903) 3 New Irish Jurist & Loc. Gov’t Rev. 76 |
Irl |
Race Relations Board v Applin |
[1973] QB 815 |
Eng |
S v Mkosiyana |
(1966) 4 SA 655 |
SA |
Samson |
[1991] 2 QB 130 |
Eng |
Scott v Metropolitan Police Commissioner |
Eng |
|
Shaw v DPP |
Eng |
|
Shergill |
[2003] CLY 871 |
Eng |
Simmonds |
(1967) 51 Cr App R 316 |
Eng |
State v Henthorn |
581 N.W.2d 544 (Wis.App.1998) |
US |
State v Otto |
629 P.2d 646 (1981) |
US |
State v Reeves |
(1996) 916 S.W.2d 909 |
US |
The People (Attorney General) v Capaldi |
(1949) 1 Frewen 95 |
Irl |
The People (Attorney General) v England |
(1947) 1 Frewen 81 |
Irl |
The People (Attorney General) v Keane |
(1975) 1 Frewen 392 |
Irl |
The People (Attorney General) v O’Connor and O’Reilly |
(1943) 1 Frewen 42 |
Irl |
The People (Attorney General) v Sullivan |
[1964] IR 169 |
Irl |
The People (Attorney General) v Thornton |
[1952] IR 91 |
Irl |
The People (DPP) v Douglas and Hayes |
[1985] ILRM 25 |
Irl |
The People (DPP) v Murtagh |
[1990] 1 IR 339 |
Irl |
The People (DPP) v O’Brien |
Court of Criminal Appeal, 17 June 2002 |
Irl |
The People (DPP) v T |
(1988) 3 Frewen 141 |
Irl |
The State (DPP) v Walsh |
[1981] IR 412 |
Irl |
Tibbits |
[1902] 1 KB 77 |
Eng |
United States v Bruno |
(1939) 105 F 2d 921 |
US |
United States v Dege |
(1960) 364 US 51 |
US |
United States v Oviedo |
525 F.2d 881 (5th Cir.1976) |
US |
Weaver v State |
42 SE 745 (1902) |
US |
Widdowson |
(1985) 82 Cr App R 314 |
Eng |
Yip Chiu-cheung v R |
[1994] 2 All ER 924 |
Eng |
1.
This Consultation Paper forms part of the Commission’s Third
Programme of Law Reform 2008-2014,[1]
under which the Commission is committed to examining, and exploring reform
options for, the inchoate criminal offences of attempt, conspiracy and
incitement. This project complements other work by the Commission in
criminal law, including its examination of homicide[2] and defences in criminal law.[3]
2.
The Commission’s work on criminal law should also be seen against the
wider background of the codification of Ireland’s criminal law. The
Criminal Law Codification Advisory Committee[4] has been established by the Oireachtas to
oversee the development of a process of codification in Ireland. The
Committee’s First Programme of Work 2008-2009[5] states that the Advisory Committee
intends to publish an inaugural Draft Criminal Code Bill consisting of a
General Part and a Special Part.[6]
The General Part comprises the principles and rules of criminal liability that
apply generally to criminal offences (such as the physical and fault elements
and general defences), while the Special Part contains the details for specific
offences, such as offences against the person, and theft and fraud
offences. The inchoate offences of attempt, conspiracy and incitement
belong to the General Part because they relate to, and can attach to, all the
specific offences in the Special Part of the criminal law.[7] The Advisory Committee has included
these inchoate offences in the General Part of the inaugural Draft Criminal
Code Bill which it intends to publish under its First Programme of Work
2008-2009.[8]
The Commission is very pleased to be working closely with the Advisory
Committee and, in this way, contributing to the development of the inaugural
code instrument.[9]
3.
The inchoate offences addressed in this Consultation Paper are the
common law offences of attempt, conspiracy, and incitement that attach to
specific special part offences. “Inchoate” comes from the Latin word
“inchoare,” which means “to start work on.” Inchoate offences criminalise
behaviour that is working towards, or leading up to, the completion of a crime.
If you request another to murder someone you may be committing incitement to
murder. This inchoate offence is committed regardless of whether the
murder is actually carried out. Likewise, if two or more people agree to
murder someone they may be committing conspiracy to murder, and for this no
actual murder is required to take place. Finally, if someone tries to
cause death by their own means, but the intended victim does not die, they may
be guilty of attempted murder.
4.
Murder is the special part offence here. Each of the three
inchoate offences may attach to this special part offence depending on the
facts. Inchoate offences are parasitic on special part offences.
There is no such thing as an offence of simply “attempt”; criminal attempt is
always attempt to do something criminal. Lawyers and academics may talk
about attempt and criminal attempts without mentioning what is being attempted;
this Paper does so. What is being discussed here are the contours of
attempt liability, that is, the common features of attempted murder, attempted
theft, attempted burglary, attempted rape, and all the other conceivable
attempt offences.
5.
Inchoate offences do not exist in isolation. An inchoate offence
comes into existence only when it combines with one or more of the special part
offences. Attempt and incitement always attach to a crime.
Conspiracy always attaches to either a crime or an unlawful activity.
Unlawful activity for the purpose of conspiracy has a particular meaning and is
wider than “criminal”. It should be also noted that there are a number of
conspiracy offences that are really special part offences. Conspiracy to
defraud and conspiracy to corrupt public morals are examples.
6.
Generally, if a new special part offence comes into existence, then
inchoate offences relating to that substantive offence also come into
existence. Suppose, for example, a new statutory offence of adultery is
enacted. This would have the effect of creating inchoate offences of
attempting, inciting, and conspiring to commit adultery. It is noted that
Article 15.2.1° of the Constitution of Ireland vests exclusive law-making power
in the Oireachtas. The process described in the adultery example here
does not conflict with Article 15 since it would be the Oireachtas, not judges
causing attempt, conspiracy, and incitement to commit adultery to come into
existence. Just as self-defence would be a defence to any new offence
enacted in the absence of the enacting statute providing otherwise, so too
would attempt, conspiracy, and incitement relate to any new offence enacted.
7.
The
label “inchoate offences” can be used to describe not just attempt, conspiracy
and incitement when they attach or relate to special part offences, but also
many special part offences that have the character of criminalising conduct
that leads to prohibited harm. Central examples of special part offences
that can reasonably be called inchoate offences are possession offences.[10] Possession of a knife in public[11] is a special part offence on the statute
book. Yet mere possession causes no actual prohibited harm such as injury
or the fear of attack. Carrying a knife may increase the likelihood of
criminal harm, or it may be thought that carrying a knife in public is a
prelude to offences such as assault and robbery. By prohibiting mere
possession in public, the law aims to stamp out conduct leading to substantive
criminal harm. Thus it has a similar function to attempt, conspiracy, and
incitement, though in this particular instance the special part inchoate
offence (possession of a knife) catches conduct further removed from the
completion of substantive criminal harm than criminal attempt liability
would. Accordingly, this special part inchoate offence can be thought of
as supplementing the general part inchoate offences.
8.
Inchoate liability in the wide sense means the attribution of criminal
liability for conduct leading to, but not occasioning, the resulting harm that
the criminal law prohibits. This includes special part inchoate offences
as well as the general part principles allowing for attempt, conspiracy, and
incitement to attach to special part offences. The narrower meaning of
inchoate liability includes only the latter – that is, attributing liability
for attempting, inciting, or conspiring to commit particular offences.
This can be called relational liability. Relational liability is a subset
of inchoate liability. Relational liability is the focus of this
Consultation Paper; it is concerned with attempt, incitement and conspiracy as
relational offences that attach to – and are entirely parasitic on –
substantive special part offences.
9.
Another note about the scope of this Consultation Paper is that it
focuses on the substantive law of general part inchoate offences. That
is, the descriptions of the constituent parts of attempt, conspiracy, and
incitement. Significant procedural issues arise regarding these
offences. There are rules of evidence unique to conspiracy, for example.
These procedural issues are not, however, within the scope of this
Paper. Neither are questions of punishment for these offences. It
is envisaged that by initially focusing exclusively on the substantive law of
inchoate offences, the Commission can best serve Ireland’s process of codification.
This takes account of the recommendation of The Expert Group on Codification of
the Criminal Law that the first phase of codification should include a
comprehensive statement of general part principles[12] and this statement should not be
cluttered with procedural rules.[13]
10.
This Consultation Paper begins with discussion of the relational inchoate
offences and their place in the criminal law. It then proceeds to address
attempt, conspiracy and incitement. This particular sequence reflects a
movement outwards from the occurrence of substantive criminal harm, attempt
being closest to the completion of a substantive special part offence,
incitement typically furthest away.[14]
11.
Chapter 1 explores the nature of inchoate offences. It gives a
brief account of the history of inchoate offences and their rationale. It
then discusses criminal law theory engaged by inchoate offences, namely
principles of legality, objectivist and subjectivist perspectives, and
principles of mens rea. Then follows a discussion of how inchoate
liability relates to, and differs from, secondary liability. Next, the
operation of inchoate offences in practice in Ireland is surveyed. The
Chapter concludes with discussion of considerations relevant to the task of
codifying inchoate offences.
12.
Chapter 2 focuses on criminal attempts, describing current Irish law on
attempt by separating attempt into three components: actus reus, mens
rea, and the target or goal of an attempt. The target of an attempt
refers to the special part offence that the attempt relates to. For each
section, reform options are evaluated and provisional recommendations are set
out. Chapter 2 also discusses, in the context of criminal attempts,
issues that apply to all three inchoate offences. These issues include
the scope for inchoate offences to attach to other inchoate offences (double
inchoate liability). Also discussed is the relevance of impossibility and
abandonment to inchoate liability. The Commission makes a number of
provisional recommendations for the law of criminal attempt. These
provisional recommendations amount to a codification of attempt law as it is.
Though it is acknowledged there is substantial uncertainty as to
precisely what the existing law in Ireland is. To sum up the Commission’s
provisional recommendations for attempt: the actus reus of attempt is an
act proximate to the completion of the target special part offence, the mens
rea of attempt is intention, and neither impossibility nor abandonment are
a defence to a charge of attempt.
13.
Chapter 3 is on criminal conspiracy. Following the structure of
the previous Chapter it sets out Irish law on conspiracy, highlights
problematic aspects, and then evaluates other jurisdictions’ approaches as well
as arguments for reform. Chapter 3 deals with what might be called
substantive or special part conspiracy offences such as conspiracy to
defraud. These conspiracy offences differ from conspiracy as an inchoate
offence that attaches to special part crimes in that they are free-standing
full special part offences in themselves. Case law on these offences
does, however, employ and indeed develop the law on conspiracy generally since
the same concept of agreement is used. For the most part the Commission
provisionally recommends a codification of existing conspiracy law. To
sum up, the Commission provisionally recommends conspiracy is an agreement to
commit a crime whether or not the crime is the primary purpose of the agreement
or a side effect of pursuing the agreement; that so-called impossible
conspiracies are still conspiracies; and that withdrawal from a conspiracy is
not a defence. The significant provisional recommendation for law reform
in relation to conspiracy is that conspiracy be limited to agreements to commit
crime. The Commission provisionally recommends, therefore, that it no
longer be the case that agreements to pursue unlawful, though non-criminal,
activity constitute criminal conspiracy.
14.
Chapter 4 is on incitement. Again, it follows the structure of the
previous Chapters in that it aims to set out the existing law and then survey
and evaluate options for reform. Some issues that arise only with
incitement are discussed. These include a perceived gap in incitement
liability and the relationship of incitement to free speech principles.
The Commission’s provisional recommendations for incitement are to codify
the existing common law position. The Commission, therefore,
provisionally recommends that the actus reus of incitement be defined as
“commands, encourages, or requests”; that the mens rea of incitement be
intention; that only crimes can be incited; and that neither impossibility nor
withdrawal is a defence to incitement.
15.
Chapter 5 lists the Commission’s provisional recommendations.
16.
This Consultation Paper is intended to form the basis of discussion and
therefore all the recommendations made are provisional in nature. The
Commission will make its final recommendations on the subject of inchoate
offences following further consideration of the issues and consultation with
interested parties. Submissions on the provisional recommendations
included in this Consultation Paper are welcome. To enable the Commission
to proceed with the preparation of its Final Report, those who wish to do so
are requested to make their submissions in writing by post to the Commission or
by email to info@lawreform.ie by 30 May 2008.
1.01
This Chapter explores the nature of inchoate offences. It gives a
brief account of their history and rationale. The Chapter explains the
relevance of some aspects of criminal law theory to inchoate offences. In
particular those aspects are legality, objectivist and subjectivist
perspectives, and mens rea. The similarity and the difference
between inchoate liability and secondary liability are outlined. Also, a
picture of the operation of inchoate offences in practice in Ireland is
provided. Finally, the Chapter considers the tension between achieving
certainty and allowing flexibility in the codification of inchoate offences.
1.02
Inchoate liability in the wide sense means the attribution of criminal
liability for conduct leading to, but not occasioning, prohibited
consequences. The criminal law imposes this inchoate liability by having
specific offences such as possession of firearms in what is known as the
special part of the criminal law. The criminal law also has general part
principles allowing for attempt, conspiracy, and incitement to attach to
special part offences and thereby expanding their scope. The narrower
meaning of inchoate liability includes only the attribution of liability for
attempting, inciting, or conspiring to commit particular offences. This
is called relational inchoate liability or simply relational liability;[15] it is a subset of inchoate liability in
the wide sense. Relational liability is the focus of this Paper; it is
concerned with attempt, incitement and conspiracy as relational offences that
attach to special part offences.
1.03
Relational liability as understood today – that is, attempt, incitement,
and conspiracy available to attach to special part offences – is a relatively
recent development in the story of inchoate liability in the wide sense.[16] In the late 18th
Century there was judicial recognition that every crime necessarily entails
criminal liability for attempting it.[17] R v Higgins,[18]
at the beginning of the 19th Century, was handled by the judges as a
case of criminal attempt. It was, however, a classic case of incitement –
the defendant solicited a servant to steal his master’s goods. It can be
seen, therefore, as establishing incitement as a distinct inchoate offence that
will attach to special part crimes.
1.04
Specific conspiracy offences go back many centuries. An example of
a specific conspiracy from the 14th Century is conspiracy to
maintain false pleas or cause children to maintain false pleas.[19] A modern day specific conspiracy
is conspiracy to defraud.[20]
Sayre reports an interesting case from as far back as 1351 where it seems
a general conspiracy charge that would relate to a substantive wrong was
charged but refused recognition by Shardlowe J.[21] McAuley and McCutcheon interpret
the failure of the charge as revealing the specific nature of conspiracy at the
time and indeed for the centuries that followed.[22]
1.05
The first identification of conspiracy as a relational offence that
would attach to all other specific crimes and indeed non-criminal wrongs may
have been in the 18th Century in the writings of Hawkins and
Blackstone.[23]
Sayre doubts Hawkins was accurately describing the existing law,[24] McAuley and McCutcheon doubt Blackstone
was.[25] R v Journeymen Tailors[26] employed conspiracy as Hawkins and
Blackstone described, that is, as something that could attach to a yet to be
specified wrong, though this case subsequently became an authority for a
specific offence amounting to conspiracy to strike. The seminal 19th
Century authority for conspiracy cited in modern courts and textbooks is R v
Jones,[27] which identifies conspiracy in its pure
relational form as an agreement to do an unlawful act or a lawful act by
unlawful means.
1.06
Inchoate offences have two main rationales. One rationale points out
how the person who attempted, incited, or conspired to murder is just as
morally culpable as the person who committed murder. The fortuitous event
of the victim not dying can be thought to cause no reduction in the
blameworthiness of those who intended him dead by their own hands or by the
hands of another. One judge in 2007 when sentencing for an attempted
murder is reported as saying that he failed to see why the defendant should
“avoid a life sentence merely because [he] is a bad shot”.[28]
1.07
Another rationale of inchoate offences maintains that law enforcement
agents should be able to step in before crimes are completed and still be able
to process the would-be perpetrators through the criminal justice system.
It is thought that the goal of harm prevention is better pursued if this is so,
rather than if law-enforcement agents have to wait until the crime is completed
before intervening if they want prosecution to be possible. Putting it
another way, one writer asserts, “society should not be required to choose
between prevention of the crime and prosecution of the offender.”[29]
1.08
Neither of these rationales is adequate on its own. If the moral
culpability rationale was the sole rationale, why is it that intending harm or
hoping for it or other wicked thoughts are not punishable? It is not just
evidential difficulties that stand against such a possibility; our criminal law
does not aim to criminalise all bad people but rather, for the most part, bad
people who cause harm.
1.09
Consistent pursuit of the harm prevention goal alone would require
serious thought be given to criminalising such behaviour as leaving one’s own
bicycle unlocked in the street, displaying valuable items in public and so
on. Though there are many examples in criminal law of extending liability
out from the already wide range of relational inchoate liability, the mere
tendency to lead to criminal harm does not of itself make conduct appropriate
for criminalisation.
1.10
It has been argued that conspiracy has a unique rationale among the
inchoate offences.[30]
It is said that the rationalisation of conspiracy is not to be found in
an account of criminalising conduct that leads to crime. If criminalising
conduct leading to crime is the only rationale in play, then it would suggest
preparatory acts of a single actor should be criminal also.[31] Rather, the rationalisation of
conspiracy is based on the seriousness of the choice the conspirator makes when
he or she exchanges one obligation (to obey the law) for another (the criminal
enterprise that he or she agrees to).[32]
It
is one thing for a lone actor to discontinue on a criminal path, it’s quite
another matter where an actor is part of a criminal group. Add to this
the observations about how criminal gangs, as opposed to individuals, can
achieve economies of scale in criminal enterprise and there emerges a picture
of a conspiracy as a particularly dangerous threat of criminal harm of
significant magnitude.[33]
1.11
Undoubtedly conspiracy is the odd one among the three inchoate offences;
that it can relate to non-criminal wrongs as well as crimes makes it unique as
a general part entity. Conspiracy can transform clearly non-criminal
conduct into something criminal. Of course, principles of secondary
liability render seemingly innocuous behaviour, such as giving somebody a lift,
into a crime if such behaviour was done knowing a crime was being assisted
(driving the person to a shop that they will rob). But this behaviour is
clearly connected to a crime (in this case, robbery). With
conspiracy there may be no crime. The peculiarity of conspiracy warrants
questioning of the justification of conspiracy. The arguments for restricting
conspiracy to agreements to commit crime are examined in Chapter 3.
Restricting conspiracy in this way would bring its rationale more in line with
that of attempt and incitement.
1.12
The legality principle is a foundational principle of modern criminal
law. It can be stated in various ways.[34] One formulation says that persons
should be convicted and punished for doing X only if they in fact did X and X
was clearly and accessibly marked out in advance as something that is
prohibited and that can result in punishment. This legality principle
forms the core of “the rule of law” which applies to all law – not just
criminal law – and is fleshed out with principles including: law should not be
retroactive, it should be accessible, capable of being obeyed, stable, and
certain, applied in practice consistent with how it is promulgated and so on.[35] The rule of law is concerned with
respecting citizens’ autonomy and freedom. When the law is certain and
applied as it says it will be applied, citizens can lead self-shaping lives
enjoying maximum freedom. Certainty in law provides security for citizens
to rely on the law to be enforced for their protection and not to their
detriment provided they keep within its boundaries.[36]
1.13
The legality principle has played a crucial role in informing the
Commission’s recent recommendations for criminal law.[37] It is also a driving force
presupposed in current processes to codify the criminal law.[38] This Paper will pay much attention
to the legality principle, especially when considering reform of conspiracy.[39]
1.14
Tension between subjectivism and objectivism is engaged by inchoate
offences. Broadly speaking, subjectivists[40] recommend that criminal defendants be
punished on the basis of their responsibility and culpability for criminal
harm. Objectivists[41]
say this concern should be tempered with recognition of the actual harm people
have caused. Inchoate offences uniquely do not, or need not, occasion
actual criminal harm. Thus objectivists argue for narrow inchoate
offences while subjectivists argue for wider. While subjectivism tends to
work as an exculpatory doctrine – and objectivism inculpatory – when applied to
defences such as duress and self-defence, for inchoate offences the roles are
reversed. Thus an objectivist like Antony Duff proposes a quite narrow
definition for criminal attempt while Glanville Williams’ subjectivist approach
recommends a wider criminal attempt.[42]
1.15
Generally, criminal law operates so that specified acts (or omissions)
are prohibited. If these acts are done with a culpable or guilty mind
liability, specified punishment may result. Punishment is imposed because
a (criminal) harm was caused by an actor with a guilty mind. In contrast,
inchoate offences serve to punish on the basis of, at most, risked or
threatened criminal harm posed by an actor with a guilty mind. With
inchoate offences the emphasis on the aspects on the offence is the reverse of
what is typical in criminal law. That is, the guilty mind of the accused,
rather than his or her physical actions, is the most important part of an
inchoate offence. Indeed, his or her actions by definition will not
satisfy the actus reus of the substantive offence to which the inchoate
offence charged relates, for otherwise the substantive offence is the
appropriate charge. Of course, the evidence in a case of attempted
murder, for example, will often also tend to suggest the commission of lesser
offences such as assault. But this is not necessarily the case.
People who plan shoplifting most likely do not commit any substantive special
part offence, though they commit the inchoate offence of conspiracy to commit
theft.[43]
The actions that constitute a criminal attempt may be innocuous if viewed
without reference to the guilty mind. For incitement and conspiracy the
actions are typically mere communications.
1.16
Some textbook writers reverse their usual order of approach when writing
about inchoate offences and thus discuss mens rea before actus reus.[44] As Duff states, “[i]t is
commonplace that the analysis of criminal attempts must begin with the mens
rea or fault element. In an attempt, ‘the intent becomes the
principal ingredient of the crime’.”[45]
1.17
There are two ways in which a person can be held criminally liable where
he or she did not in fact completely perform a special part offence.[46] One way is by relational inchoate
liability – a person can be convicted of attempt, conspiracy, or incitement
where the target special part offence is not completed by them or indeed by
anyone. The other way is by secondary liability. Where a person
aids, abets, counsels or procures the commission of an indictable offence they
can be tried and convicted as if they themselves committed that offence.[47] This means that a person can be
found guilty of a special part offence even though what they did does not
satisfy the definition of offence. An illustrative example is the getaway
driver for a bank heist. The driver does not in fact perform the acts
that constitute robbery (appropriating another’s property by force); the driver
just helps those who do. Yet the driver may be convicted of robbery.
In this case secondary liability serves to widen out or amplify the reach
of special part offences. This is also what relational inchoate offences
do. Relational inchoate liability and secondary liability are how the
general part expands liability for special part offences. In this
respect, secondary and inchoate liability have the opposite function to the
general defences such as self-defence and duress because these defences serve
to restrict or negate liability for special part offences.
1.18
The crucial difference between inchoate liability and secondary
liability is that for the secondary liability a special part offence is
necessarily completed, while for inchoate liability it is not necessary that
any special part offence is completed. Textbooks and other academic
writing thus treat inchoate liability and secondary liability separately.
But in practice the two areas overlap, particularly with incitement and
conspiracy. If one person incites another they will be inchoately liable,
but this will transform to secondary liability if the other person goes on to
commit the incited crime. In Chapter 4 on incitement there is discussion
of the appropriate way for the criminal law to address those who encourage,
assist, or direct crimes that they do not themselves perform.
1.19
It can be noted that just as new special part offences in statutes have
served to widen out the range of inchoate liability, so too they have widened
out secondary liability. Statutory derivative liability does this.
An example is section 58 of the Criminal Justice (Theft and Fraud Offences)
Act 2001,
which grounds derivative liability where a corporate offence “is proved to have
been committed with the consent or connivance of, or to have been attributable
to any neglect on the part of” an officer.[48] There is a range of conduct that
might not have satisfied the secondary liability requirements of “aid, abet,
procure, or counsel” but would satisfy this “consent, connivance, or neglect”
requirement.
1.20
The Annual Reports of the Director of Public Prosecutions (DPP) provide
records of offences directed for prosecution in the Central Criminal Court and
the outcome of these prosecutions. Combining the data in the 2004, 2005,
and 2006 Annual Reports, there were four prosecutions for attempted murder in
the five year period, 2001-2005. A number of recent attempted murder
cases will increase this number in future reports.[49] In the same period there were 195
prosecutions for murder. Of the four attempted murder prosecutions, two
resulted in convictions on a guilty plea, one in conviction for a lesser
offence, and for one there is no data.
1.21
On no occasion in the four year period, 2002-2005, did a prosecution for
murder result in a conviction for attempted murder, though 41 of the 159 murder
prosecutions in that same period resulted in convictions for lesser charges,
other than attempted murder, such as manslaughter and assault causing
harm. This confirms what might have been supposed: that attempted murder
does not function as a “fall-back” charge for foundering murder prosecutions.
1.22
For the five year period, 2001-2005, there were seven directions for
prosecution for attempted rape. In the same period the number of
prosecutions for rape was 298. Of the seven attempted rape prosecutions,
one resulted in conviction by the jury, two resulted in convictions on guilty
pleas, one in conviction for a lesser offence, and for three there is no data.
1.23
On two occasions in the four year period, 2002-2005, what started as a
rape prosecution resulted in conviction for attempted rape. In the same
period there were eight convictions for a lesser offence, other than attempted
rape, resulting from 164 rape prosecutions. Here, attempted rape differs
from attempted murder in that it does seem to serve a limited “fall-back”
function for rape prosecutions that do not succeed. One might venture to
explain this by reference to the difference between murder and attempted murder
being the death of the victim, and whether a victim has died or not can be
proved with certainty. In contrast, it is not so easy to prove the fact
distinguishing rape from attempted rape, that fact being sexual penetration.
1.24
Attempted burglary and attempted robbery are subsumed under burglary and
robbery respectively, and are therefore not distinguished in the DPP’s
statistics. The Commission, nevertheless, understands that outside of the
Central Criminal Court, prosecutions for attempted burglary and attempted
robbery commonly feature in the Circuit Criminal Court.
1.25
Inchoate offences in the wide sense means all those offences that
criminalize conduct leading to, but not occasioning, the harm that society
seeks to prevent through the use of criminal law. Inchoate offences in
the wide sense, therefore, includes attempting, inciting or conspiring to
commit crimes. It also includes many stand alone special part offences in
statutes, such as possession offences and endangerment offences. These
may be called statutory inchoate offences.
1.26
Statutory inchoate offences feature more frequently than the common law
inchoate offences of attempt, conspiracy, and incitement attaching to
substantive crimes. Examples include:
· Possession
of a firearm without a firearm certificate.[50]
· Possession
of a knife in public.[51]
· Dangerous
driving.[52]
1.27
The 2006 Annual Report of the Courts Service details the offences
disposed of in the Special Criminal Court. The offences are:
· Membership
of an unlawful organisation.[53]
· Possession
of an explosive substance.[54]
· Possession
of an explosive device.[55]
· Possession
of ammunition.[56]
1.28
Each of these four offences is an example of an inchoate offence in the
wide sense. The occurrence of any substantive harm is not
necessary for conviction for any of these offences. Rather, the conduct
criminalised by these offences is conduct that is perceived as tending to lead
to substantive harm or the threat of substantive harm.
1.29
On many occasions academic writers have criticised the overuse of
conspiracy.[57]
Perhaps this is a reaction to the criticism that conspiracy is the
prosecutor’s “darling”[58]
since, among others things, it triggers a relaxation of evidential rules
such as hearsay. This criticism does not, however, seem to apply to
Ireland at the moment. Among guidelines for prosecutors set out by the
DPP are specific considerations when charging conspiracy. Under section
titled “Choice of Charge” the DPP states:
“Conspiracy charges are generally not appropriate where the
conduct in question amounts to a substantive offence and there is sufficient
reliable evidence to support a charge for that offence. But there are occasions
when to bring a conspiracy charge is the only adequate and appropriate response
on the available evidence. Where it is proposed to lay or proceed with
conspiracy charges jointly against a number of accused, the prosecutor should
be aware of the risk of the trial becoming unduly complex or lengthy.”[59]
1.30
Evident here is a principled reluctance to charge conspiracy – it is
only to be charged out of necessity; it is bad practice to charge conspiracy
where substantive charges could be laid. Nevertheless, conspiracy has
historically been charged where a substantive offence has indeed been
completed. Conspiracy is committed by a mere agreement, and it is not the
kind of agreement that will be recorded. A conspiracy because of its
nature may be unlikely to come to the attention of state officials and there is
often insufficient evidence without acts on foot of the conspiracy to reveal
its existence.
1.31
Codification of inchoate offences engages a tension between certainty
and flexibility. In aiming for certainty and precision when defining
inchoate offences, particularly attempt, a price is paid in that the law
becomes rigid.[60]
A rigid law tends to bind the court to reaching unwanted decisions,
either because it criminalises behaviour that should not be criminal or fails
to criminalise behaviour that should be criminal. The code-drafter seems
to be left in a difficult position: to opt for certainty at the cost of
flexibility, or to allow flexibility at the cost of certainty. It can be
argued, however, that the position is not so difficult because the second
option, flexibility at the cost of certainty, does not involve the destruction
of the benefits associated with certainty that might be thought.
1.32
It is accepted that certainty in the criminal law is a good thing.
It is a key part of the legality principle set out above.[61] Often certainty is seen as a good
in itself, and this may be so. But the principal value of certainty in
law lies in its instrumental value. One account of the good of certainty
in law points out that it makes for more efficient handing of cases in court
thus making justice less costly to the State and to litigants. This
explanation continues, explaining why it is a good thing to keep the cost of
justice down – it might ultimately boil down to the good of equality or liberty
– this does not matter for present purposes. The point is that certainty
in law is not the point at which the explanation ends. Another account of
the good of certainty in law claims that it allows people to rely on the
law. If citizens can be reasonably confident about how the law will be
applied then they have greater scope to plan their lives, pursue their goals
with coherent plans; the more certain law is, the more confidently it can be
relied on and thus the greater liberty people have to pursue self-shaping
lives. Certainty is an instrumental good, not an end in itself.
1.33
If the substantive criminal law indicates with certainty what conduct is
liable for criminal sanction, then citizens enjoy greater freedom than they
would enjoy were substantive criminal law to be vague and uncertain. Of
course, there are more aspects than just certainty that need to be present if
this goal of substantive criminal law is to be achieved. The substantive
criminal law needs to be relatively stable, it needs to be promulgated and
accessible, and must not be so onerous as to be incapable of being complied
with, and so on.[62]
The drafter of a particular provision of the criminal code chiefly
contributes to this overall effort through precision of drafting. For
example, special part offences such as theft and fraud offences need to be
known by someone conducting business – such a person needs to know what they
must not do in order to avoid incurring a criminal penalty. The more
precise these offences are drafted in a Code, the better.
1.34
Now, turning from substantive special part offences to inchoate
offences, it is suggested that the drive for certainty is different in an
important way. As has been remarked on in detail above,[63] inchoate offences attach to substantive
offences. Their existence is essentially relational or parasitic.
It is the substantive special part offences that people need to know (or at
least are able to find out quickly and inexpensively) so that they can avoid
committing them. When citizens know they cannot do these offences then
they know there is no gain, but only danger, in attempting, conspiring, or
inciting these things. There is no additional benefit to be gained regards
shaping your life from being able to know precisely at what point you become
criminally liable when you plan and prepare and then execute a bank heist.[64] By definition there is no money to
be made in an attempted bank robbery.
1.35
The value of certainty in defining inchoate offences is more limited
than the value of certainty in defining substantive offences. This should
be borne in minding when striving to make inchoate offences certain.
Similarly, the legality principle is not so constraining regarding defining the
excusatory defences[65]
as it is regarding justificatory defences such as legitimate defence.[66]
2.01
It is criminal to attempt to commit a crime. Haugh J in The
People (Attorney General) v Thornton described a criminal attempt as “an act done by
the accused with specific intent to commit a particular crime.”[67] This definition has three
components:
i)
“an act” (the actus reus)
ii)
“intent” (the mens rea)
iii)
“a particular crime” (the target of the attempt).
2.02
This Chapter describes these three components in detail and evaluates
different approaches to defining criminal attempt. It also addresses the
issues:
i)
whether a criminal attempt is committed where it is not possible to
complete the target substantive offence (impossibility)
ii)
whether a person who ceases in their attempt at crime thereby becomes
not liable for attempt (abandonment).
2.03
The law on attempt liability in Ireland is found in case law. An
attempt to commit a statutory offence is still a common law offence.[68] Describing the law involves setting out
the Irish courts’ interpretation of the common law. For some aspects,
however, there is no Irish judicial comment and therefore non-Irish courts’
interpretation of the common law is of particular relevance.
2.04
A number of substantive offences have their related attempt offence
provided for in statute. Attempted murder is provided for in section 11
of the Offences Against the Person Act 1861. Strictly speaking,
this provision is unnecessary because once murder is an offence known to the
law, the offence of attempted murder automatically exists. An advantage
of codifying inchoate offences will be to remove whatever doubts about their
existence that motivate the enactment of specific inchoate offences.
2.05
|
|
At common law it is settled that an act is
necessary for criminal attempt; mere intention to commit a crime is not
criminal.[69] Also settled at common law is that merely
preparatory acts cannot constitute the act necessary for an attempt.[70] Beyond this there are differing
and much debated approaches to defining the actus reus. It has
been noted many times how difficult it is to provide a formula or definition
that will distinguish attempt from mere preparation.[71] As the Law Commission for England
and Wales recognised, “there is no magic formula which can [ ] be produced to
define precisely what constitutes an attempt.”[72]
2.06
This section endeavours to identify the actus reus of attempt in
Irish law. It also evaluates different approaches to defining the actus
reus before setting out the Commission’s provisional recommendations.
2.07
Four basic approaches to defining the actus reus of attempt have
been developed. Each approach proposes a test for identifying the act of
a criminal attempt.
i)
Proximity theory requires an act close to completing the target
substantive offence.
ii)
The “first act” approach is satisfied with any act towards the
completion of the target offence.
iii)
The “last act” approach requires the defendant to have done every act
necessary on his part to bring about the completion of the target offence.
iv)
An unequivocal act approach requires the act to unambiguously bear its
criminal intent on its face.
2.08
The first three approaches
impose liability at different points along the range between beginning to act
on an intention to commit a crime and completing that crime; the proximate act
lying somewhere in between the first and last acts. The unequivocal act
approach differs in that it is not range-based. Rather, it expects the
act to have an intrinsic quality. The unequivocal act approach is perhaps
best understood as motivated by a concern to have an actus reus of
attempt that confirms the mens rea. Thus, it is said that under
the unequivocal act approach the primary purpose of having an “act” requirement
is evidential. The act confirms that the mind is indeed a guilty one.
The first three approaches are mutually exclusive in that it would be
incoherent to combine the first and last act approaches with each other.
Nor would it make sense to combine either the first or last act approaches
with the proximate act approach. But the unequivocal act approach can
coherently be combined with any one of the others.
2.09
In The People (Attorney General) v Sullivan[73] the Supreme Court held that the
defendant could rightly be tried for attempting to obtain money by false
pretences. The defendant was a midwife who was contracted to be paid a
basic salary for attending 25 births in a year. For additional births
beyond 25 she would get additional pay. She had submitted some reports of
fictitious births. There was no evidence whether she had reached or
exceeded the 25 mark. Accordingly, the Court assumed, in her favour, she
had not. The question was whether she had done enough at this point
(having submitted just three false reports) to be guilty of an attempt given
that she would in the end receive the extra pay only if her reported cases within
the contract year exceeded 25? Were her actions attempt rather than mere
preparation? In answering yes, the Court held that each and every false
claim submitted was “sufficiently proximate” to committing the substantive
offence in order to constitute the physical element of attempt.[74]
2.10
This decision is seen as a straightforward application of proximity
theory,[75]
which holds that the act done towards the target offence must be close to
completion of the target offence in order to be a criminal attempt.
Indeed, Walsh J, speaking for the Supreme Court in Sullivan,
stated what he called “the proximity rule” to decide the case, quoting Parke B
in R v Eagleton as expressing this rule in the negative form:
“acts remotely leading towards the commission of the offence
are not to be considered as attempts to commit it, but acts immediately
connected with it are”[76]
2.11
An act “immediately connected with” the commission of an offence could
reasonably be considered not just a proximate act, but actually a last act.
Of course, the passage quoted above does not say that only acts
immediately with commission are attempts; it can be read as illustrating the
proximity rule by stating how last acts most certainly qualify as attempts
under the proximity rule. This is Walsh J’s reading of Eagleton.
However, Eagleton has been read by other courts, and by commentators, as
setting out a last act test.[77]
The last act reading has much plausibility when Parke B’s judgment is
quoted more expansively than the Supreme Court in Sullivan did.
The passage above continues:
“if, in this case, … any further step on the part of the
defendant had been necessary to obtain payment … we should have thought that
the obtaining credit would not have been sufficiently proximate to the
obtaining the money. But … no other act on the part of the defendant
would have been required. It was the last act, depending on himself,
towards the payment of the money, and therefore it ought to be considered as an
attempt.”[78]
2.12
The Law Commission for England and Wales suggest this passage was
“probably not intended to be a statement of law to be applied in all cases.”[79] Whatever the exact intention
behind it, this passage reveals the ratio of Eagleton: an attempt
is committed when the defendant has performed the last act needed on his part
to bring about the substantive offence. The word “proximate” is used, but
it is used in a quite restrictive sense.[80] Sullivan, strictly
speaking, did not apply Eagleton, for in Sullivan the Court held
that there could be a criminal attempt notwithstanding there being more acts on
the part of the accused needed to complete the substantive offence. The
additional acts needed in Sullivan were the submission of further birth
reports, whether real or fictitious, so as to exceed 25 births for the contract
year.
2.13
The case of The People (Attorney General) v England,[81] like Sullivan, applies a
proximity test. The defendant had talked about an unspecified house in
Dublin where “pornographic practices” took place and, so the witness claimed,
invited the witness to attend this house. Gavan Duffy P, speaking for the
Court of Criminal Appeal, held that the defendant’s conviction for attempting
to procure an act of gross indecency could not stand because the action of the
accused “was not, in fact, near enough to the actual criminal procurement of
[the witness] to constitute in law the attempt to procure charged in the
indictment.”[82]
2.14
The England is not an authority for the proposition that mere
words cannot constitute an attempt.[83]
There are numerous scenarios where mere words would satisfy even the stringent
last act test for attempt. For example, an adult instructs a child do a
criminal act. The child is incapable of the crime; hence, an incitement
charge is not appropriate. But there may be a criminal attempt here since
the adult has tried to commit a substantive offence through the agency of the
innocent child.
2.15
In The People (Attorney General) v Thornton[84] the accused had been convicted of
attempting to procure a poison to bring about a miscarriage. The accused
had made a girl pregnant. While a doctor was examining this girl the
accused asked “wasn’t there something called ergot?” In the opinion of
the Court of Criminal Appeal though this could, as a matter of probability, be
construed as an attempt to get an abortion, the communication was ambiguous and
thus could not be considered an attempt.[85] The conviction was quashed.
A version of the unequivocal act requirement forms the ratio of Thornton
since the reason why a prosecution for attempt could not lie in Thornton,
according to the Court of Criminal Appeal, was because more than one inference
could be drawn on viewing the act of the accused
2.16
The People (Attorney General) v Thornton[86] could be described as applying an
unequivocality requirement. Yet no express endorsement of unequivocal act
approaches was made in Thornton. Furthermore, Haugh J endorses
proximity theory:
“[the act] must go beyond the mere preparation, and must be a
direct movement towards the commission after the preparations have been made …
and if it only remotely leads to the commission of the offence and is not
immediately connected therewith, it cannot be considered as an attempt to
commit an offence.”[87]
2.17
This is the Eagleton formula, interpreted by the Supreme Court in
Sullivan as suggesting simply a proximity test. But the Eagleton
formula can be, and has been, read as suggesting a last act test.
Requiring the act to be “immediately connected” with the commission of the
offence can plausibly be another way of saying that a last act is
required. It is true that “the Irish law on criminal attempts embraces
the proximity theory.”[88]
But proximity theory is not the only approach discernible in Irish cases.
2.18
Proximity theory requires a proximate act for criminal attempt. A
proximate act is one that is close to the commission of the full target
offence. A proximate act stands in contrast to a remote act; the latter
will not suffice for attempt liability. In R v Button[89] the defendant lied in order to get a
favourable handicap for some running races, which he went on to win. The
defendant’s deceit was discovered prior to the stage of his claiming the prize
money. It was held that his acts were close enough to obtaining money by
false pretences and thus he could be convicted of attempting that offence.
2.19
The Eagleton formula has been read as applying a proximate act
test and also as applying a last act test. Perhaps this reveals that
these two tests are really the same thing. The Law Commission for England
and Wales pointed out that the literal meaning of proximate is “nearest, next
before or after (in place, order, time, connection of thought, causation etc”.[90] Adopting this meaning for
“proximate” and the result is that “proximate act” is just another way of
saying “last act”.[91]
However, it is apparent that for the most part in recent times, when
judges and commentators use “proximate act” they do not mean to restrict their
subject matter to last acts.[92]
Furthermore, “proximity” is much used in tort cases, and it is clear that
in tort proximity is not restricted to meaning right beside, or immediately
beside something.
2.20
The main advantage of the proximate act approach over other tests is
also, strangely, its chief disadvantage. That is, its vagueness and
indeterminacy allows a court flexibility to avoid reaching unacceptable results
in individual cases. First and last act tests tend to criminalise,
respectively, too much and too little. The proximate act test allows a
court to steer clear of these extremes. It enables the court to provide a
legally justified decision that will accord with the court’s sense of a just
result.
2.21
The indeterminacy of the proximate act test is demonstrated by asking of
any case applying the test whether it could have been used to reach the
opposite conclusion.[93]
Consider the leading Irish case, The People (Attorney General) v
Sullivan.[94]
The Supreme Court said each submission of a fictitious birth report by the
defendant midwife was sufficiently proximate to the substantive offence of
obtaining money by false pretences. But the Court could easily and
plausibly have said that each fictitious birth report was not sufficiently
proximate given that the midwife still had much work to do – submit more than
25 reports within a year[95]
– before she was in a position to claim and receive pay for work she did not
do. There is substantial distance, both in terms of quantity of work
(more reports, whether real or false) and time (up to a whole year), between
the acts of the accused for which she stood trial and the completion of the
substantive offence. The point is that the Sullivan decision could
have gone the other way and still be an entirely reasonable application of the
proximate act approach.
2.22
With some confidence it can be said that the first and last act
approaches, if applied to Sullivan, would result, respectively, in
conviction and acquittal. But predicting which way a Sullivan type
case would go on the proximate act approach cannot be done with any confidence
because the proximate act approach does not constrain judicial decisions.
Rather, it provides a way for judges to make their decision sound constrained
in law. McAuley and McCutcheon say it “looks more like a guide than a
true test”.[96]
Guides do not bind their users as to where to go.
2.23
The last act is the final thing the defendant needs to do in order for
the full offence to happen. In DPP v Stonehouse[97] the defendant faked his death so that
his wife, who was unaware of her husband’s plan, could collect insurance
money. Citing the Eagleton requirement for an act “immediately
connected” with the full offence Lord Diplock said that the “offender must have
crossed the Rubicon and burnt his boats.” The defendant was guilty of
attempt, according to the House of Lords, because he had done all the physical
acts necessary on his part to result in his wife getting the insurance money.
2.24
The last act test promises certainty. The problem is that the more
the last act approach is geared towards pursuing the goal of certainty the less
it serves the purpose of having inchoate offences in the first place.
This is because the last act test needs to be applied strictly in order to give
certainty. But when it is applied strictly it results in an extremely
restricted law of criminal attempts.
2.25
Duff claims Stonehouse is not really a literal application of the
last act test.[98]
To ensure his wife would get and keep the insurance money Stonehouse
himself had to evade detection, something he in fact failed to do. The
same point can be made about other supposed last act cases. This literal
application is needed if the last act approach is to have the certainty it
promises. For otherwise it will collapse to something like the proximate
act approach, which does not give the formula to pick out precisely what is and
what is not the actus reus of an attempt in any given set of facts.
2.26
Yet with the literal application of the last act approach we see just
how restrictive it is. Does it even catch the classic case of the shooter
who misses her intended victim? The last act required is that the
would-be murderer shoots her victim, but, in contrast to where the intended
victim is wearing a bullet proof vest or otherwise survives despite the bullet
hitting him, where the shot is simply off target the last act – send a bullet at
the intended victim – has not been done. When sentencing for an attempted
murder in 2007, de Valera J said he failed to see why the defendant should
“avoid a life sentence merely because [he] is a bad shot”.[99] This sentiment applies, with even
stronger reason, to the issue of whether it is attempted murder where the
shooter misses having intended to kill his target. This is precisely the
scenario where attempt liability should attach and yet a strict last act test
would suggest otherwise. Duff cites attempted theft and attempted rape as
attempt crimes that will no longer exist if a strict last act test is applied
since the very act needed to make out the attempt – the last act – is precisely
the same act that makes the substantive crime complete.[100] Criminal attempt is made
redundant.[101]
2.27
It could be said that these statements about how last act theory applies
in practice are incorrect, that you can convict for attempted murder the
shooter who misses his victim under the last act test, as well as the would-be
rapist who fails to complete rape solely because of impotence. But
insofar as this is the case, then the last act approach has lost its chief
attribute, namely, the promise of certainty and consistency in picking out
criminal attempts.
2.28
The supposed benefit of certainty gained by a last act test over a
proximate act test comes at the cost of not pursuing the aim of having inchoate
offences in the first place. This aim being consistent moral punishment
(why should the person who tried and failed to commit rape get an aggravated
sexual assault conviction rather than an attempted rape conviction?) and the
prevention of criminal harm (we want the police when possible to stop would-be
car thieves before they make off in the car).
2.29
The “first act” is any act towards the commission of the target
offence. In R v Schofield[102] the defendant, intending to burn down a
house, had placed materials and a lighted candle under the stairs.
Although the defendant had progressed well beyond the “first act,” the
following dictum of Lord Mansfield can be read as endorsing a first act
test:
“…if it is coupled with an unlawful and malicious intent,
though the act itself would otherwise have been innocent, the intent being
criminal, the act becomes criminal and punishable.”[103]
2.30
A number of code provisions from around the world embody versions of
first act tests for attempts. Queensland’s Criminal Code
of 1899 is an example. Section 4(1) provides:
“When a person, intending to commit an offence, begins to put
the person's intention into execution by means adapted to its fulfilment, and
manifests the person's intention by some overt act, but does not fulfil the
person's intention to such an extent as to commit the offence, the person is
said to attempt to commit the offence.”[104]
2.31
The use of “begins” in this provision indicates the first act
suffices. However, the act still has to be “overt” and must manifest the
person’s intention. So not all conceivable first acts will suffice.
A more pure form of a first act test is section 22 of the German Penal Code,
which defines attempt:
“An attempt to commit a crime occurs when a person, in
accordance with his conception of the crime, moves directly toward its
accomplishment.”[105]
2.32
James Fitzjames Stephen wrote,
“[A]n act done with intent to commit a crime, and forming
part of a series of acts, which would constitute its actual commission if it
were not interrupted.”[106]
This can be read as a first act test; the act can be at any
stage (including, therefore, the first) in the series of acts. The Law
Commission for England and Wales read Stephen’s test this way.[107]
Yet Duff argues that Stephen’s test endorses proximity theory rather than
first act theory.[108]
In any event, this approach did not find much favour with the courts; it
is inconsistent with the requirement that the conduct element of an attempt be
more that mere preparation.
2.33
The first act approach vigorously pursues the rationale of inchoate
offences, whether that rationale be located chiefly in the crime prevention or
moral punishment goal, because it enables police to step in at any stage after
the first act towards the substantive crime is committed and prosecute the would-be
perpetrator. This approach to inchoate liability does not logically lead
on to requiring criminal intent alone to be an inchoate crime. The
physical element (the first act) is still required as a matter of evidence –
the act is insisted on as a reassurance that the intention is real, that is,
doing the act corroborates the existence of the criminal intent.[109]
At trial there must be evidence suggesting the requisite intent and also
that an act was done in furtherance of that intent.
2.34
Glanville Williams commended the logic of the first act approach:
“Any act done with the fixed intention of committing a crime,
and by way of preparation for it, however remote it may be from the crime,
might well be treated as criminal. The rational course would be to catch
intending offenders as soon as possible, and set about curing them of their
evil tendencies: not leave them alone on the ground that their acts are mere
preparation.”[110]
2.35
With a first act test the range of attempt liability would be very
large. Many people harbour criminal intentions which they never pursue
and thus they cause no criminal harm. Yet the first act test stands ready
to criminalise people the very minute they take one act towards committing a
crime no matter how much additional work would be needed. The man who
looks up strangulation methods on the internet intending to strangle his wife
commits attempted murder. There are problems with this. It
criminalises conduct very far away from substantive criminal harm.
Perhaps the encroachment on liberty is too much a price to pay for the marginal
gains in harm prevention.[111]
2.36
There is an additional rule of law objection. A legal system
cannot possibly detect and enforce criminal law that prohibits such a wide
range of behaviour as that rendered criminal under the first act
approach. And it is costly to try – police and court time is used up on
trivial crimes. Left with un-enforced criminal law there results
disparity between application of law in practice and the law as
promulgated. Selective police enforcement results, which has a corrupting
effect.[112]
It becomes incumbent on police to turn a blind eye to things. The
more they have to do this, the more scope for corruption. It is not that
these undesirable circumstances do not happen as things are, or do not happen
so long as a first act test for attempts is declined; the point is that the
tendency for these bad things increases with letting the criminal law net
become more and more all-catching.
2.37
The act needed to satisfy the physical element of attempt according to
the “unequivocality” theory is one that cannot be regarded as having a purpose
other than the commission of the target offence. This theory was proposed
by Sir John Salmond; in his words the physical act of the attempt must be
“unequivocally referable” to he intention to commit the target offence.[113]
Salmond said a criminal attempt should bear “criminal intent upon its
face. Res ipsa loquitor.” Thus, it can be seen that Salmond’s test
is motivated by seeking to have an evidential confirmation of the criminal
intention to commit substantive crime.
2.38
The New Zealand Appeal Court, of which Salmond was a member, put this
theory into practice in R v Barker.[114]
The defendant was caught leading away a young boy to whom he had promised
“good fun.” The defendant later admitted he intended to commit
buggery. Salmond J said the physical act of a criminal attempt must be
such that on its own it is evidence of the particular criminal intent.
The act must bear its criminal intent on its face. The act in Barker,
according to Salmond J, did indeed manifest the admitted intention; an objective
observer of the defendant’s actions would see no explanation for the conduct
other than pursing the relevant sexual assault. This approach was applied
subsequently with some modification in New Zealand in a number of cases,[115]
but was expressly abolished by statute in 1961, which states “[a]n act done or
omitted with intent to commit an offence may constitute an attempt if it is
immediately or proximately connected with the intended offence, whether or
not there was any act unequivocally showing the intent to commit that offence”.[116]
2.39
The English Court of Appeal’s judgment in Davey v Lee[117] has been seen as endorsing the unequivocal
act approach.[118]
A translation of the Italian Penal Code provision on attempt reads
“Anyone who does acts aptly directed in an unequivocal manner towards
commission of a crime shall be liable for an attempted crime…”[119]
In United States v Oviedo[120] it was said that the act must
corroborate the mens rea:
“[W]e demand that in order for a defendant to be guilty of a
criminal attempt, the objective acts performed, without any reliance on the
accompanying mens rea, mark the defendant’s conduct as criminal in
nature. The acts should be unique rather than so commonplace that they
are engaged in by persons not in violation of the law.”
The reason for this was evidential, that is, to prevent
conviction of the innocent on the basis of inferences from possibly unreliable
testimony and the history of the defendant.
2.40
McAuley and McCutcheon identify the chief weakness of the unequivocality
approach as its likelihood of leading to unmeritorious acquittals.[121]
The concern is that on a charge of attempting a specific offence the
defendant will escape liability if it can be demonstrated that his actions were
capable of being viewed as trying to achieve something other than the target
offence specified in the indictment. Glanville Williams illustrated this
point with the example of the man found kneeling beside a corn stack with pipe
in mouth and matches in hand.[122] Even with independent evidence of
intent to burn the corn this man evades attempt liability since his act is
equivocal: it is ambiguous between trying to set fire to the corn and trying to
light his pipe. This is how the pure unequivocality approach as developed
and subsequently abolished in New Zealand applies. Evidence of mens
rea in the form of a confession goes to establish mens rea only and
is not to be used to help establish the actus reus.
2.41
The test can be watered down, and thereby not allow so much
unmeritorious evasion of liability, by allowing independent evidence of mens
rea to resolve equivocality about the defendant’s act. Thus, in light
of the man beside the corn stack later admitting an intention to set fire to
the corn, his act is no longer equivocal. Rather, it can now be seen as
an unequivocal act towards the target offence. Italian courts have taken
this approach.[123]
This approach has also been discerned in the English Court of Appeal’s
decision in Jones v Brooks.[124]
The defendant brothers had been acquitted at trial of attempting to take and
drive away a car without the owner’s consent. They were not charged with
attempted theft of a car; their “confession” disclosed only an intention to
“borrow” a car in order to get home. A police constable had observed one
of them try without success to open a locked Ford Anglia with unsuitable keys
and then duck down when his brother keeping watch called out a warning.
Later, one of the defendants admitted to police that they were seeking to borrow
a car in order to drive themselves home. The Court of Appeal accepted
that if the expressed intention to borrow a car was ignored then the act of
trying to enter the car was equivocal between a number of possible aims
including theft or sleeping in the car.[125] But, according to the Court, the
expressed intention should be considered as a relevant circumstance which can
help reveal what aim the otherwise equivocal act was directed towards.[126]
2.42
As McAuley and McCutcheon recognise, the Court in Jones did not
really apply the unequivocality test, or at least what the Court applied is not
the distinctive unequivocality test developed in Salmond’s writings.
Rather, the Jones Court’s watered down version of unequivocality is
really a proximity test. The very fact that that the Court had to use the
defendant’s mens rea to render his attempt-act unequivocally directed
towards achieving the target offence reveals that the Court considered the
attempt-act equivocal when viewed on its own.[127] The Court of Appeal
in Jones do indeed say the actus reus must be “sufficiently
proximate” to the target offence and thus lead one to wonder what is remarkable
about claiming that Jones applied a proximity test rather than an
unequivocality test? The answer is that there are two reasons why Jones
could or would be seen as taking the unequivocality approach. First,
the unequivocality test can be applied in addition to a proximity test.[128]
Second, Jones was decided under the authority of the then one-year-old
case of Davey v Lee,[129]
which is indeed an example of the unequivocality approach.
2.43
Section 1(1) of the Criminal Attempts Act 1981 states:
“If, with intent to commit an offence to which this section
applies, a person does an act which is more than merely preparatory to the
commission of the offence, he is guilty of attempting to commit the offence.”
2.44
This provision is identical in substance to the recommendation of the
Law Commission for England and Wales. The Law Commission’s Draft Bill
provision[130]
on the actus reus of attempt read “If, with intent to commit a relevant
offence, a person does an act which goes so far towards the commission of that
offence as to be more than a merely preparatory act…” The actus reus
of a criminal attempt is a “more than merely preparatory” act. Thus the
1981 Act put the common law rule that mere preparation for crime by a single
actor is not criminal on a statutory basis. It also based the definition
of attempt on this rule.
2.45
Glanville Williams suggested that a “proximate act” and a “more than
merely preparatory” act are much the same thing; the latter phrase just being
more cumbersome.[131]
Though the Law Commission aimed to recommend a formula that would express
the existing common law[132]
– which relied on the notion of proximity – it eschewed the use of the word
“proximate” because the literal meaning of that word would make the test for
attempt too demanding.[133]
In other words, if a “proximate act” is understood as its literal
dictionary meaning then it will be understood as a last act. Williams
suggested that the dominant modern English usage of “proximate” was more like
“near” than the original Latin proximus meaning “nearest”.[134]
He could have added that, at least in recent times, when judges used
“proximate act” they mean any act near the completion of the crime, not just
acts right next to, or just before, the completion of the crime.
2.46
An advantage of the “more than merely preparatory” formula over the
proximity formula is coherence with criminalizing impossible attempts.
This is not to pre-judge the issue of whether impossible attempts should be
criminalised. The point here is that one formula more comfortably allows
for that option than does the other. It is also noted that the impossible
attempts question might refer back to the actus reus question in the
sense that it might be argued that impossible attempts should not be
criminalised because doing so goes against proximity theory.[135] For the person attempting the
impossible cannot ever be said to be near completion of what they were trying
to do. But the acts of such a person can be described as having the
quality of being “more than merely preparatory”. Consider the example of
someone shooting a dummy believing it to be the person they wish to kill.
They have not come close to killing, but they have done an act that can be
categorised as more than merely preparatory.[136]
2.47
“Merely” in the “more than merely preparatory” formula is an
important word. It is noteworthy that leading Irish judgments on attempt
include “mere” when stating the rule that mere preparation is not a criminal
attempt.[137]
Ormerod suggests that all but the very last step towards the commission of a
crime may properly be described as preparatory, an example being the would-be
assassin readying his finger on the trigger “preparing” to pull it.[138]
The 1981 Act certainly was not intended to collapse to a last act test
for attempt.[139]
Yet a number of times it has been applied as if it was a last act test.[140]
Not all
preparatory acts towards crime
are merely preparatory. Ormerod quotes Rowlatt J saying an actor is
attempting crime when he is “on the job”.[141] When you’re on the job your acts
may have the characteristic of being preparatory, but they are not “only” or
“just” or “merely” preparatory. Ormerod cites R v Tosti[142] as illustrating the significance of
“merely” in section 1 of the 1981 Act. And indeed the Court in Tosti
described acts as “preparatory, but not merely so”.[143]
2.48
But what does “on the job” mean? For Ormerod it means “attempt”.[144]
Thus, the process of applying the codified actus reus of attempt
in England appears to be circular. The 1981 Act aims to tell what a
criminal attempt is. It says it is more than merely preparatory acts
towards crime. How do the jury decide which acts are more than merely
preparatory? The answer: if they constitute attempt.
2.49
Here lies the basis of a critique of the 1981 Act articulated by Ian
Dennis in the early 1980s. Dennis criticised the 1981 Act for not giving
guidance as to what constitutes attempt,
that the “more than merely preparatory” test is even more open-textured than
the common law tests and that the 1981 Act presents as a rule what is really a
principle that merely preparatory acts should not be criminalised as attempts.[145]
The Act does not tell the tribunal of fact how to distinguish between
merely preparatory acts and something more.
2.50
Perhaps, though, what Dennis laments as imprecise – and Ormerod refrains
from criticising – is a good thing, for it bases the law of attempts on the
ordinary meaning of attempt. Yet if basing attempt law on the ordinary
meaning of attempt is what is desired why did the Law Commission for England
and Wales not just propose a statutory provision providing, bluntly, that
attempting to commit crimes is criminal, and that this it is for the jury to
decide? Dennis canvassed this possibility as “[o]ne radical answer” but,
we may add, an answer nonetheless. That so many courts and experts
proclaim the intractable elusiveness of a precise formula for identifying
criminal attempts may be because such a formula does not exist. If it
does not exist then settling for the simple ordinary language description of
attempt is a sensible option.[146]
2.51
The “more than merely preparatory” test suffers a similar weakness to
that of the proximity test. That is, many acts could be described as
merely preparatory, but they could also be described as more than merely
preparatory. The problem is apparent in R v Campbell.[147]
The defendant was apprehended as he was about to enter a Post Office with
an imitation gun, sunglasses, and a threatening note. The Court of Appeal
held that because he had yet to enter the place of the intended robbery, the
defendant’s acts had not progressed beyond mere preparation and thus could not
be considered a criminal attempt to commit robbery. This decision has
been criticised for undermining police efforts to prevent crime since it means
they must – if a prosecution for attempt is to be achieved – hold off
intervening.[148]
The decision also illustrates the malleability of the “more than merely
preparatory” formula because the judges’ choosing of the perimeter of the Post
Office building as the dividing line between mere preparation and attempt was
not something mandated by the text of the 1981 Act. Again, the Court’s
decision could be otherwise and yet claim with at least equal plausibility to
be consistent with the 1981 Act. That is, in walking purposely towards
the Post Office door the defendant could be said to have advanced beyond the
merely preparatory acts of equipping himself with a fake gun and robbery note.
2.52
Further illustration of this indeterminacy criticism is provided by
contrasting R v Geddes[149] with R v Tosti.[150]
In Geddes the defendant had been in a boys’ school toilet in
possession of, among other things, a knife and rope. The Court of Appeal[151]
held what the defendant had done was not beyond mere preparation and
accordingly quashed his conviction for attempted false imprisonment. In Tosti
the defendants had run off when seen examining a barn door padlock. They
had metal cutting equipment hidden in a nearby hedge and their cars close
by. The Court of Appeal[152] held that the acts of the defendants
were more than merely preparatory and their conviction for attempted burglary
could stand.
2.53
It is difficult to say that any of Campbell, Geddes, or Tosti
are incorrect interpretations of the 1981 Act, though strong criticisms of Campbell
and Geddes could be made by reference to the practicalities of crime
prevention (that is, catching and being able to prosecute would-be offenders
before citizens become endangered). Worth noting is that the Tosti
Court emphasised the word “merely” in the “more than merely preparatory”
formula. As recognised in various editions of Smith and Hogan[153]
placing importance on the inclusion of “merely” can help alleviate
indeterminacy somewhat, for it brings realisation that all acts right up to
commission of crime can, from some light, be viewed as preparatory, but
not quite as many acts can be viewed as merely preparatory.
2.54
The American Law Institute’s Model Penal Code (“MPC”) section 5.01, in
much truncated form, reads:
“A person is guilty of an attempt to commit a crime if … he …
purposely does or omits to do anything which … is an act or omission
constituting a substantial step in the course of conduct planned to culminate
in his commission of the crime.”
Guidance is given on what is a “substantial step”:
“Conduct shall not be held to constitute a substantial step …
unless it is strongly corroborative of the actor’s criminal purpose.”
2.55
Yet further guidance on what is to be considered a substantial step that
is strongly corroborative of the actor’s criminal purpose is provided by
illustrative examples:
“lying in wait for, searching out or following the contemplated
victim of the intended offence;
enticing or seeking to entice the contemplated victim of the
intended offence to go to the place contemplated for its commission;
reconnoitering the place contemplated for the commission of
the intended offence;
unlawful entry of a structure, vehicle or enclosure in which
it is contemplated that the offence will be committed;
possession of materials to be employed in the commission of
the offence which are specifically designed for such unlawful use, or which can
serve no lawful purpose in the circumstances;
possession, collection or fabrication of materials to be
employed in the commission of the offence, at or near the place contemplated
for its commission, where such possession, collection or fabrication serves no
lawful purpose in the circumstances;
soliciting an innocent agent to engage in conduct
constituting an element of the offence.”
2.56
The MPC provision is notable for the wideness of the range of conduct it
can be used to identify as attempt. The “substantial step” is not far
removed from the “first act”. Furthermore, the illustrative examples set
out include acts that would not have been considered an attempt at common law
because they are merely preparatory. Consider R v Campbell[154]
(defendant caught about to enter Post Office with imitation gun, sunglasses
and threatening note), for example, in light of the MPC’s “possession of
materials” example. Or R v Geddes[155] (defendant caught in boys’ lavatory
with kidnapping materials) in light of the MPC’s “enticing or seeking to
entice” example. People v Rizzo[156] was an application of the common
law, which the “searching out” of a victim example was included in order to
reverse.[157]
2.57
The MPC’s drafting technique of using illustrative examples has the
merit of giving practical guidance to courts, juries, and indeed police and
citizens on when the threshold of attempt is crossed. Dennis argued that
a list of illustrative examples should have followed the England and Wales
Criminal Attempts Act’s definition of attempt.[158] The Law Commission for England
and Wales have suggested the use of examples in its latest proposals for an
offence of criminal preparation.[159]
2.58
The use of illustrative examples may serve to clutter up the criminal
code. And this might be especially undesirable in the general part of the
code in that the specificity of the illustrative examples is out of character
among general principles of liability. This concern about cosmetics
perhaps could be addressed by moving the list of illustrative examples to an
appendix to a criminal code. More difficult to address are concerns about
illustrative examples undermining the central definition of attempt. The
illustrative examples are not meant to be exhaustive, nonetheless their
existence may raise doubt about would-be attempt scenarios not included.
2.59
Given that the use of illustrative examples in criminal statue in
Ireland would be entirely novel, compelling arguments are needed for the idea
to gain momentum. These are not apparent. Finally, it is noteworthy
that recent re-codification proposals in the United States have moved away from
the MPC’s method of including illustrative examples for attempt and incitement[160]
and that existing criminal codes in the United States employing the MPC’s
definition of attempt do not have the MPC’s illustrative examples.[161]
Section 24 of The Criminal Code of Canada provides,
“(1) Every one who, having an intent to commit an offence,
does or omits to do anything for the purpose of carrying out the intention is
guilty of an attempt to commit the offence whether or not it was possible under
the circumstances to commit the offence.
(2) The question whether an act or omission by a person who
has an intent to commit an offence is or is not mere preparation to commit the
offence, and too remote to constitute an attempt to commit the offence, is a
question of law.”
This text is almost identical to the text of Canada’s
original Criminal Code of 1892, which was based on the English Draft Code of
1879, which was drafted by James Fitzjames Stephen, whose drafting aimed to
codify the common law.[162]
2.60
Section 24(1) provides that doing or omitting to do anything for
the purpose of carrying out an intention to commit crime is an attempt.
Thus from this provision alone it looks as if Canada adopts the wide first act
(and omission) test for attempts. However, section 24(2) indicates that
mere preparation is not criminal. Hence, section 24 puts on a statutory
footing what was already settled at common law, namely, that an act is required
for an attempt, but a merely preparatory act is not enough.
2.61
Of the four approaches
– proximity, first act, last act, and unequivocality – the criticisms of the
proximity approach are the least compelling. Thus, the approach that most
likely represents the law in Ireland[163] is also the approach with the least
serious problems.
2.62
The first act approach draws the net of criminal
liability too widely, both from a practical point of view and a moral point of
view. Both the last act approach and the unequivocality approach, in
their pure forms, disserve the rationale of inchoate offences. In trying
to rescue these approaches one arrives at a proximity approach.
2.63
One option is to
supplement a proximate act approach with a version of an unequivocality
requirement. This is arguably the most accurate way to codify the
existing law on attempt in Ireland in light of the Court of Criminal Appeal’s
decision in The People (Attorney General) v Thornton.[164]
The following statement
from an old edition of Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice
expresses a proximate act approach tempered with an unequivocality requirement:
“It is
submitted that the actus reus necessary to constitute an attempt is
complete if the prisoner does an act which is a step towards the commission of
the specific crime, which is immediately and not merely remotely connected with
the commission of it, and the doing of which cannot reasonably be regarded as
having any other purpose than the commission of the specific crime.”[165]
2.64
What formula of words
should be used to codify the proximate act approach? This boils down to a
choice between using the word “proximate” or either of “more than merely
preparatory” or “not remotely connected with…”. Using “proximate” is simpler
and avoids the tangles that the others can lead to given that they are negative
definitions. Any promise of greater certainty in the more convoluted
formulations is illusory. Additionally, a proximate act definition can be
consistent with impossible attempts constituting attempts since the evaluation
of the proximate act will be made from the actor’s perspective rather than an
objective bystander’s perspective.
2.65
The Commission
provisionally recommends codification of the proximate act approach to defining
the actus reus
of attempt and invites submissions on which formula of words should be used.
2.66
The Commission invites submissions on whether a list of illustrative
examples should accompany a definition of attempt.
2.67
It is accepted that there should be attempt liability for an omission
where the target special part offence is one that can be committed by omission.[166]
The classic example is trying to starve a baby by omitting to feed it.[167]
There has been comment on conceptual difficulties with the notion of
attempting by omission,[168]
but really these concerns are no different to the concerns with liability for
omission per se; no extra difficulty is added by the notion of attempt. It just has to be remembered that attempt
by omission attaches only to a special part offence only in
circumstances where that special part offence may by committed by
omission. What should a code provision on attempts say about attempted
omissions or attempting by omission? Some Code provisions do not
explicitly refer to omissions,[169] some do.[170]
2.68
The Law Commission for England and Wales has recently addressed this
issue.[171]
The Law Commission for England and Wales endorses its previous
recommendation[172]
that a code provision on attempt should explicitly provide that an omission may
constitute an attempt where the special part offence attempted is one that can
be committed by omission. That this is so might be thought so obvious as
to not need to be included in a code provision on attempt.
2.69
The Commission invites submissions on whether there should be
explicit recognition that where a substantive offence can be committed by
omission, attempting that offence can also be committed by omission.
2.70
This Consultation Paper does not purport to address criminal procedure
for inchoate offences. But some procedural issues get caught up in the
statutory definition of the substantive law. Some statutory provisions on
attempt[173]
expressly deal with whether the jury or the judge ultimately decides if the
evidence establishes a criminal attempt. These statutory provisions do
this by specifying whether the existence of an attempt is a question of law or
a question of fact.
2.71
If the existence of an attempt is a question of law the procedure is that
the judge decides whether the facts (as accepted by the jury) are sufficient to
constitute an attempt. The procedure is the same as this if the existence
of attempt is a question of fact, save for one significant difference: the jury
get to second guess (and possibly overrule) the judge’s opinion whether
particular facts (if accepted) amount to a criminal attempt.
2.72
In The People (Attorney General) v England[174] Gavan Duffy P upheld the trial judge’s
decision that the facts disclosed in evidence could not in law amount to a
criminal attempt. This suggests an understanding of attempt as an issue
of law, for otherwise the Court of Criminal Appeal would have said that the
matter should have been left to the jury even if the trial judge considered the
evidence incapable of establishing attempt liability. In England and
Wales prior to the Criminal Attempts Act 1981 the House of Lords, applying the
common law, indicated the question of attempt was one of fact.[175]
This approach was recommended by the Law Commission for England and Wales[176]
and codified in the Criminal Attempts Act 1981.
2.73
The Law Commission for England and Wales now considers the approach in
the 1981 Act to be problematic in that the jury get to interpret the law and
conceivably could decide that a clear case of attempt (last act having been
performed, requisite mens rea established) was not an attempt.
This would be a departure from the usual procedure in criminal trials.[177]
2.74
It makes sense to opt for the approach in the UK Criminal Attempts Act
1981 to the fact/law issue only if it is sought to avoid having a precise
substantive definition of attempt whereby the question of what is an attempt is
left to be decided by the jury on a case by case basis. This is the
option canvassed by Ian Dennis in 1980,[178] though it is clear that Dennis
mentioned this option as one that might be opted for out of exasperation with
the elusiveness of a definition of attempt. It follows that once it is
sought to have a legal definition for attempt it makes sense to have the issue
of attempt one of law. There is no reason to depart from standard
criminal procedure save in the exceptional scenario of having attempt liability
decided by juries on an ad hoc basis unconstrained by legal parameters.
2.75
The Commission provisionally recommends that the issue of what can
constitute a criminal attempt should be a question of law.
2.76
Another procedural requirement that may have impact on substantive law
is that a conviction for a particular offence precludes a conviction for
attempting that particular offence. This is an example of where a
seemingly procedural law can have a bearing on the substantive law; that is,
where prosecution has to prove (1) an intent to commit a specific crime; (2) an
overt act toward the commission of that crime and (3) a failure to consummate
the crime.[179]
It is not necessary that attempt be defined this way in order to preclude
conviction for both an offence and its attempt.
2.77
Some criminal codes expressly rule out conviction for the target
offence if there has been conviction for attempting it.[180]
In any event, it is quite clear that conviction for the target offence of
an attempt precludes conviction for its attempt and vice versa.[181]
It is probably not necessary for a code provision on attempt to state this.
2.78
In late 2007 the Law
Commission for England and Wales published “Conspiracy and Attempts – a
Consultation Paper”.[182]
The main recommendation relevant to the actus reus of attempt is
Proposal 15, which proposes that the offence of attempt be split into two
offences: an offence of attempt and an offence of criminal preparation.
The actus reus of attempt is the doing of the “last acts” towards
completing a crime. The actus reus of criminal preparation is
“conduct preparatory to the commission of an offence”, but this conduct “must
go sufficiently far beyond merely preparatory conduct so as to amount to part
of the execution of the intention to commit the intended offence itself.”[183]
These proposed offences carry the same mens rea requirement and the same
punishment (in that punishment relates to the target offence, but does not have
to be more if the offence was attempted rather than prepared).
2.79
The Law Commission for England and Wales consider the application of
attempt in England and Wales under the Criminal Attempts Act 1981
unsatisfactory. The Court of Appeal’s decision in R v Geddes[184]
illustrates, for the Law Commission for England and Wales, the unduly
restrictive scope of criminal attempt that the 1981 Act has put in place.
In Geddes an attempt was held, on appeal, not to be made out where the
defendant had entered the lavatory in a boys’ school equipped with materials
useful in effecting a kidnap. The Court of Appeal viewed the defendant as
having readied himself to make a kidnap but not having actually tried to do
so. Thus the requirement of an act more than merely preparatory to the
commission of the offence was not satisfied.
2.80
The key motivation for the two-offence proposal of the Law Commission
for England and Wales is to preserve the label “attempt” given its value in
conveying much about the actor’s culpability and dangerousness, while also
making sure that the conduct that just falls outside the ordinary meaning of
“attempt” is still caught by means of the criminal preparation offence.
The latter was intended to be caught by the 1981 Act, according to the Law
Commission for England and Wales, but the more than merely preparatory formula
as applied in Geddes results otherwise.
2.81
The proposed attempt offence relies on the notion of “last acts”.
It is “last acts”, not “last act”. The plurality of last acts refers not
to the last act in an attempted murder plus the last act in an attempted theft,
and so on, but rather to the last few acts in any one offence. So, for
example, the last acts of murder might include the taking aim with a gun and
the pulling of the trigger. When there is more that one last act towards
a particular offence it is questionable whether “last” is an accurate word to
use. If “last act” is not restricted to the very last single act, then
there is not really a last act requirement.
2.82
The proposed offence of criminal preparation is a strange offence.
In sum, its actus reus is “more than merely preparatory
preparation”. It seems strange to label an offence something – here,
criminal preparation – that does not constitute the offence in its pure
form. The offence X is not committed where all that is done is X.
2.83
Strange this may be, there is nothing illogical about it. There
really does exist more than merely preparatory preparation, referred to also as
“executory preparation”.[185]
With the Law Commission for England and Wales’ proposal to provide illustrative
examples of criminal preparation as a guide this can be appreciated. The
proposed offence of criminal preparation is to include, but is not limited to,
the following:
“(1) D gains entry into a building, structure, vehicle or
enclosure or (remains therein) with a view to committing the intended offence
there and then or as soon as an opportunity presents itself.
(2) D examines or interferes with a door, window, lock or
alarm or puts in place a ladder or similar device with a view there and then to
gaining unlawful entry into a building, structure or vehicle to commit the
intended offence within.
(3) D commits an offence or an act of distraction or
deception with a view to committing the intended offence there and then.
(4) D, with a view to committing the intended offence there
and then or as soon as an opportunity presents itself:
(a) approaches the intended victim or the object of the
intended offence, or
(b) lies in wait for an intended victim; or
(c) follows the intended victim.”[186]
2.84
If it is desired to catch this type of conduct as criminal the question
is whether the concept of attempt, coupled with the numerous special part
offences that criminalise preparatory acts, achieve this?
2.85
The Commission invites submissions on whether a general offence of
criminal preparation is desirable.
2.86
An attempt involves trying to do something; trying to do something
usually means that the something is intended.[187] Of course, trying to do something
does not necessarily mean you intend it. An example of trying to do
something without intending it is kicking a toughened glass window in order to
demonstrate its toughness. You are trying to break it, but you intend it
not to break.[188]
2.87
Haugh J in The People (Attorney General) v Thornton[189]
described a criminal attempt as an act done with “specific intent to commit a
particular crime.” For the avoidance of doubt it is worth pointing out
that “intent to commit a particular crime” does not mean that a thought such as
“I intend to commit the criminal offence of X” must be attributable to the
criminal defendant. In Ireland, as elsewhere, criminal liability is
imposed regardless of whether the accused knew that what he or she was doing
was criminal. The maxim “ignorance of the law is no excuse” generally
applies. The accused who pleads, no matter how sincerely, that they did
not know that what they were doing was criminal is generally not entitled to
any relief from liability. That the accused did not know or realise their
act was prohibited may well effect their treatment by the criminal justice
system at stages other than trial for liability, for
example, at sentencing stage. So, strictly speaking, for an attempt the guilty person does not have
to intend to do a particular crime, but rather must intend to do an act, which
happens to be contrary to the criminal law.
2.88
There are two significant aspects of Haugh J’s description of the mens
rea of attempt. First, intent, rather than other states of mind
(recklessness, negligence) is required. Intention in this respect is
direct intention. Direct intention can be identified by asking how an
actor feels about a consequence not materialising.[190] So if the enquiry is whether an
actor’s (direct) intention was to kill, then the question to ask is whether the
actor would have considered what he did a failure if a killing did not
result. In attempt liability, even where the target offence is one for
which a state of mind different from intent suffices, the person allegedly
attempting that target offence must intend to commit it in order to be guilty
of criminal attempt. The substantive offence of endangerment is committed
by intentionally or recklessly engaging in conduct creating a substantial risk
of death or serious harm.[191]
But to convict for attempted endangerment it would need to be established
that the defendant intentionally engaged in the putative risky conduct (which
as it so happened created no actual risk – this being why attempt, rather than
the complete offence, is charged).
2.89
The second significant aspect of the mens rea of attempt is that
the core of the target offence must be intended. In other words, the mens
rea of attempt must relate exactly to the target offence. This
requirement can be illustrated using the example of attempted murder.
Murder requires mens rea of either intent to cause death or intent to
cause serious injury.[192]
But for attempted murder, intent to cause death is required; intent to cause
merely serious injury will not suffice. This is the common law position,[193]
which the Court of Criminal Appeal has approved in The People (DPP) v
Douglas and Hayes.[194]
2.90
In Douglas and Hayes the accused had been convicted of shooting
with intent to murder contrary to section 14 of the Offences Against the
Person Act 1861. The accused had fired shots at an occupied Garda
car. The trial judge was of the opinion that, had the shots caused death,
murder would have been committed. On this basis according to the trial
judge the section 14 offence, which does not require shots to actually hit a
person, could be made out. The Court of Criminal Appeal rejected this
reasoning and overturned the conviction.
2.91
In Douglas and Hayes the trial judge incorrectly applied the
statutory offence of shooting with intent to murder. The offence required
intent to murder; the trial judge said reckless disregard of the risk of
killing sufficed. The ratio the Court of Criminal Appeal decision
in Douglas and Hayes corrects this misinterpretation.
Additionally, obiter dictum in Douglas and Hayes clearly approves
(despite calling the situation “anomalous”) of R v Whybrow[195]
and R v Mohan,[196] which are authority for the proposition
that shooting with intent to cause no more than serious injury is murder if it
results in death, yet not attempted murder if death does not result. A
Scots authority, Cawthorne v HM Advocate,[197]
which holds, contrary to the position in England and Wales, that mens rea
sufficient for the target offence is sufficient for an attempt at that offence
was implicitly rejected by the Court of Criminal Appeal in Douglas and Hayes.
The Canadian courts formerly[198]
favoured the same approach as Scots law, but now[199] endorse the same position as Ireland
and England.
2.92
Since the Irish courts appear to endorse the position that intent alone
suffices as a state of mind for the mens rea of attempt, it follows that
crimes of recklessness cannot be attempted – that is, they are logically
precluded since one cannot intentionally try to do something recklessly.
This statement requires qualification. Consider the case of manslaughter,
which is often thought of as the most prominent example of a crime of recklessness.
Whatever about the practice in courts, attempted voluntary manslaughter – but
not attempted involuntary manslaughter – is a logically possible crime.
Voluntary manslaughter is partially excused intentional killing. The
defence of provocation, which is available to a defendant who “lost control” as
a result of something said or done by the person they killed, reduces murder to
voluntary manslaughter. Suppose having been provoked (in the legal sense)
a person tries their very best to beat their provoker to death, but yet the
provoker survives. In this case attempted (voluntary) manslaughter would
be a coherent charge. It is noted that some Australian jurisdictions have
a crime of attempted manslaughter on the statute book.[200]
2.93
There has been debate whether less culpable mental states than intent
should suffice for criminal attempt.[201] The suggestion is that the mens
rea for attempting a particular crime need only be the mens rea that
suffices for that particular crime. One argument against having mental
states other than intent is that the meaning of the word “attempt” is such that
attempts must be intended.[202]
This might be called an argument from the etymology of “attempt”.
The counter-argument says criminal law should not be held back from development
simply because of the ordinary meaning of words.[203]
2.94
Of course, the contours of criminal liability
should not be confined to tracking linguistic usage. But that is not to
deny advantages in having criminal concepts that cohere with the ordinary
meaning of the words used to describe these concepts. The legality
principle requires that citizens who are subject to laws get a fair opportunity
to conform their behaviour so as to keep within the legally permissible.
There will always be some distance between what the law actually is and the
average citizen’s knowledge of what the law is and thus there will be shortfall
in satisfaction of the legality principle. But the distance between
criminal law and citizens’ knowledge of it is reduced where there is a coincidence
between the ordinary meaning of the words used to describe criminal law
concepts and legal officials’ understanding of those criminal law
concepts. The ordinary meaning of attempt is “trying” to do
something. Trying is purposive activity. Purposive activity is
intentional activity. If attempt in criminal law keeps to intentional
activity it will, in this respect, keep close to the ordinary meaning of
attempt.
2.95
This is not the end of
the argument, but it does provide a default position such that in the absence
of persuasive reason suggesting otherwise, criminal attempt should conform to
its ordinary meaning.
2.96
The foregoing analysis
is complicated by a consideration of oblique (or indirect) intention. An
actor obliquely intends something when, though it is not their aim to bring it
about, they know it is practically certain to be a consequence of their
action. There is much debate over how exactly to define oblique intention
and there is an issue of the scope for oblique intention to slide into a form
of recklessness. This is what the House of Lords were concerned to
counter in R v Woolin[204]
where a consequence must be foreseen as a virtual certainty of an action in
order for it to have been obliquely intended. Does the intentional
activity connoted by the ordinary meaning of attempt encompass any sort of
oblique intention as distinguished from direct intention? The answer may
well be that it does not. Even when oblique intention is described with
maximum effort to distinguish it from recklessness, as per the House of Lords
in Woolin, it still falls outside the kind of intention envisaged in the
ordinary meaning of attempt. The person who plants a bomb set to explode
on an aeroplane during flight, hoping to profit from an insurance pay-off, has
the purpose to defraud, not to kill. If his purpose is not realised, we
say he tried and failed to do something. And this something is the fraud,
not the causing of deaths.[205]
2.97
The question is whether
criminal attempt should depart somewhat from the ordinary meaning of attempt in
order to have oblique intention as well as direct intention constitute its mens
rea? There is good reason to do so. In terms of culpability and
harm there is little between the person who blows up the aeroplane for monetary
gain and the person who blows it up as an act of terrorism.[206] So if the bomb does not explode –
it’s discovered and defused say – the rationale of inchoate offences is pursued
by having the law such that attempted murder could be charged rather than just
attempted theft (leaving to one side the host of other offences, possession of
explosives and so on, that may have been committed in the example).
2.98
Almost all debate about
oblique intention and its differentiation from recklessness arises out of
murder cases. Indeed, the Commission has recently published its final
recommendations for the mens rea of murder.[207] What is suitable for the special
part offence of murder is not necessarily suitable for general part attempt
liability; it is thought a bad thing when general principles of criminal law
are distorted by efforts to improve an individual offence. In any event,
the Commission’s proposals for murder involve expanding murder mens rea
to include a form of recklessness rather than an alteration of intention.
For the avoidance of doubt it is noted again that the mens rea of
attempting a crime is a distinct matter from the mens rea for the
complete crime. It makes sense to talk about reckless murders, but it
does not make sense to talk about attempted reckless murders.
2.99
The Commission
provisionally recommends that the mens rea of attempt should continue to be intention, where intention
means both direct and oblique intention.
2.100
An important distinction between consequences and circumstances is used
to enable the prosecution of attempting certain special part offences.
The offence of common law rape is non-consensual sexual intercourse knowing the
victim is not consenting or being reckless as to whether the victim is
consenting. A straightforward application of the specific intent
requirement for the mens rea of intent would indicate that attempted
rape is committed only where the accused intended to have non-consensual sexual
intercourse. This would make it difficult to secure convictions for
attempted rape given the difficulty in proving that the accused did not just
intend intercourse, but intended non-consensual intercourse. In R v
Khan[208]
the English Court of Appeal addressed this problem, holding that a conviction
for attempted rape can lie where the defendant intends intercourse while being
reckless as to the circumstances of whether the victim is in fact
consenting. That is, the mens rea of attempted rape is intent to
have sexual intercourse being reckless as to whether consent is given.
The consequence is sexual intercourse and this must be intended. The
circumstance is non-consent; the defendant need not intend this, he need only
be reckless as to it.
2.101
Distinguishing between the consequences intended and the circumstances
existing where a person attempts a crime was an innovation of a Working Party
assisting the Law Commission for England and Wales.[209] The consequences/circumstances
distinction is attractive because it provides a way of surmounting a difficulty
in prosecuting for attempted rape the defendant who was trying to have sex with
a non-consenting woman, reckless as to whether the woman was consenting.
The difficulty is that there may be no evidence, such as a confession, that the
accused specifically intended to have non-consensual intercourse.
Here is what intuitively is a case of attempted rape, not just a case of
(aggravated or not) sexual assault. This behaviour may be more accurately
described as attempted rape. The Khan approach uses the
consequences/circumstances distinction to make this description possible in
law.
2.102
A difficulty is that there is no objective method or criteria for
distinguishing consequences from circumstances. The Khan court was
satisfied that the consequence of rape is sexual intercourse and the
circumstances of rape is non-consent. Another court, however, might view
the consequence of rape as non-consensual sexual intercourse.[210]
Indeed, the crime of rape is non-consensual sex. The event
which our criminal law identifies as unwanted is non-consensual sex; it is not
that society wants to discourage sex per se yet decides only to
criminalise non-consensual sex. So why not call non-consensual sex the
consequence which the would-be rapist must intend in order to be convicted of
attempted rape? The point is that the Khan identification of the
consequence of the crime of rape is not the only defensible answer; there is
another no less defensible approach that, if taken, no longer results in
achieving the goal of facilitating prosecution for attempted rape. It is
not that the consequence/circumstance distinction led the Khan court to
the right answer; rather it is that the Khan court had a result in mind
(a legal framework that catches those reckless-as-to-presence-of-consent attempted
rapes) and the consequence/circumstance distinction provided a convenient
rationale. The Law Commission for England and Wales in 1980 stated, “to
ask in the case of every offence what is a circumstance and what is a
consequence is in our view a difficult and artificial process which may
sometimes lead to confusion.”[211]
2.103
Glanville Williams, who was a member of the Working Party who proposed
the consequences/circumstances distinction in 1973, has defended its usefulness
by employing a further distinction between result-crimes and conduct-crimes.[212]
Unlike murder, the result of which is death, rape is a conduct-crime, not
a result-crime. In response to Williams, Richard Buxton argued that
Williams’ result/conduct-crime distinction does not ameliorate the
indeterminacy of the consequences/circumstances distinction, but merely moves
the indeterminacy on to the question of whether a crime is a conduct crime or a
result crime.[213]
There is no authoritative guide to which crimes are conduct-crimes and
which are result-crimes.
2.104
Khan (and R v Pigg[214]) stand as authority for
the law in England prior to 1981. The Law Commission for England and
Wales in 1980 expressly declined to recommend the consequence/circumstance for
inclusion in statute. The Criminal Attempts Act 1981 accordingly
did not use it. The Report on Codification of the Criminal Law of 1985[215]
of the Law Commission for England and Wales again rejected it. But the
Report of 1989,[216]
having briefly noted there may be difficulty in applying the distinction,
nonetheless recommends it, commenting that it is workable for crimes such as
rape and obtaining property by deception.
2.105
The consequences/circumstances distinction may have difficulty standing
up to rigorous analysis, yet it is capable of working reasonably well in
practice. It can be employed without contradicting the aim of keeping
criminal attempt in line with the common notion of attempt as purposive
activity. That is, it is coherent to say the mens rea of attempt
is intention while allowing one of the elements – the circumstance element – of
the target offence to be satisfied by recklessness.
2.106
With codification in mind it is an open question whether the definition
of attempt requires, or should contain, an express statement of the
consequences/circumstances distinction. The attempt provision could state
without more, as per Haugh J in Thornton, that the mens rea of attempt
is intent to commit a specific crime and leave it to the courts to employ the
consequences/circumstances distinction where necessary. The
interpretation of the common law in the English cases could be cited as
persuasive authority. Alternatively, the attempt provision could
explicitly endorse the distinction. This is done in the Draft Criminal
Code for England and Wales, Clause 49(2) provides:
“[A]n intention to commit an offence is an intention with
respect to all the elements of the offence other than fault elements, except
that recklessness with respect to a circumstance suffices where it suffices for
the offence itself.”[217]
2.107
The Commission invites submissions on whether the definition of mens
rea for criminal attempt should employ an express consequences/circumstances
distinction.
2.108
It is key, and perhaps obvious, to note that criminal attempts relate or
attach to substantive (or special part) offences. A criminal attempt is
an attempt to commit a specific offence, which can be called the target
offence. Under the common law scheme of attempt liability, it is not that
some “attempts” (in the general sense of the word) are criminal. Rather,
attempting crimes is criminal. Criminal attempts are entirely parasitic
on the special part offences.
2.109
At this stage it is worth recording what the law’s view is on which
crimes it is criminal to attempt to commit, for it is not simply the case that
it is clearly a criminal attempt to attempt any and all crimes. Which
specific offences or what type of offence qualify as the target offence?
Commentators suggest that at common law it is not an offence to attempt a
summary offence, that only indictable offences can be criminally attempted.[218]
No clear authority is cited for this proposition; it seems to be just a
“generally accepted view.”[219]
Proceeding on the basis that only attempts to commit indictable offences are
criminal, some exceptions remain.
2.110
Attempt to incite is recognised at common law.[220] The classic example of attempt to
incite occurs where a communication intended to incite a crime is intercepted
and never reaches its intended recipient. Incitement is not made out
because the communication never reached its intended recipient, but on any test
for attempt, attempted incitement is made out. Some cases of attempted
incitement could be viewed as cases of incitement where it so happens that the
recipient refuses to act on the incitement.[221]
2.111
Attempt to conspire is also recognised at common law.[222] In England and Wales the Criminal
Attempts Act 1981[223]
abolished this offence. A Supreme Court decision from Canada in 2006
confirms an earlier Canadian authority in holding that there is no such crime
in current Canadian law.[224]
In thinking up examples of an attempt to conspire it seems that
incitement or attempted incitement would almost always be made out.
2.112
There is no crime of attempt to attempt because the requirement for an
act that is more
than mere preparation would not be satisfied. In addition, it can be said
that merely attempting to attempt a crime would not occasion the requisite mens
rea since aiming to bring about a mere attempt means that the target
substantive offence is not sought to be completed and, therefore,
is not intended.
2.113
In Shergill[225]
the court declined to acknowledge a crime of attempting to commit the statutory
offence of facilitating the entry of non-EU citizens into the UK.[226] This case shows judicial unease
with a relational inchoate offence attaching to what is already an inchoate
offence presented as a special part offence via its enactment in statute.
2.114
There is good reason to be uneasy about inchoate offences attaching to
other inchoate offences (“double inchoate crimes”[227] or double inchoate liability) because
such practice moves the net of criminal liability out very far from the central
prohibited harm. UK anti-terrorism legislation provides a rather extreme
example. The offence of encouragement of terrorism under the Terrorism
Act 2006 is made out, among other ways, by publishing a
statement that is understood by some members of the public to indirectly
encourage them to assist someone to prepare to train to threaten to commit acts
of violence against property in order to advance an ideological or political
aim. This description is arrived at by combining the definitions in the
statute. It sounds an absurd thing to criminalise because it is so far
removed from an actual act of terrorism. It encroaches on personal
liberty, in particular, freedom of expression. No person has yet been
prosecuted for the encouragement of terrorism offence, though it has been in
force in the UK since mid-2006. This in itself is little consolation for
those concerned about having well-constructed substantive criminal law because
it means there is great disparity between what the law says is criminal and
what is actually getting recognised as criminal by the criminal justice
system.
2.115
If double inchoate liability is thought a problem then the question is
whether judges can legitimately decline to acknowledge relational inchoate
offences attaching to some special part inchoate offences? This to be done
where there are statutory inchoate offences and general part provisions
providing for relational inchoate offences to attach to all offences.
Alternatively, the question could be put, by what criteria may judges refuse to
countenance double inchoate liability?
2.116
First of all, it is noted that some relational inchoate offences are
restated in statutes. A prime example is attempted murder, which is
codified in section 11 of the Offences Against the Person Act 1861.[228]
This is enumerating in statute what should already be available to charge at
common law. It is important to resist inferring an offence of attempt to
attempt murder just because “attempted murder” is presented in statute as a
substantive stand alone offence which attempt as a general relational offence
can attach to. An offence of attempt to attempt murder, apart from
sounding absurd, simply cannot satisfy the definition of attempt. Logic
and common sense is all a judge needs to resist recognising attempted attempts.
2.117
Incitement to incite hatred under the Prohibition of Incitement to
Hatred Act 1989 Act would
be a different matter since the incitement to hatred offence enacted in the
1989 Act is not a restatement of a pre-existing relational inchoate offence but
rather a completely new offence since the thing incited – hatred – was not, and
is not, an offence.
2.118
Given the existence of murder as a special part offence and attempt as a
relational offence ready to attach to special part offences it is, or at least
should be, unnecessary to enact a specific crime of attempted murder such as
the 1861 Act does. With codification, including explicit general part
provisions providing for attempt, conspiracy and incitement to attach to
special part offences, any remaining uncertainty about whether a specific
special part offence of attempted murder is needed is eliminated. There
is no reason for section 11 of the 1861 Act to survive comprehensive codification.
This and other offences that do no more than enumerate a particular instance of
relational inchoate liability do not require an explicit prohibition in the
general part of a criminal code from the same relational inchoate offence
attaching to them because prosecutors and judges will recognise the problem.
2.119
There remains the problem, however, of special part offences that can be
characterised as inchoate offences in the wide sense in that they proscribe
conduct that does not actually occasion the harm which the law seeks to
prevent. Possession of a knife in public is an example.[229]
This is an inchoate offence in the wide sense, but is not an instance of
inchoate relational liability since mere possession would not occasion an
attempt. Furthermore, the inchoate nature of the possessing a knife
offence is not as apparent as, say, attempted murder. There’s no logical
bar to recognising attempt, incitement or conspiracy to commit this possession
offence. The problem is with the widening of the net of criminal
liability. Assuming that injury and apprehension of injury from knives on
the streets is the central harm sought to be reduced or prevented here, the
law, in penalising mere carrying of the knife in public, catches conduct one
step removed. Criminalising the attempting, inciting or conspiring to
carry the knife in public would be catching conduct, roughly speaking, two or
more steps removed.
2.120
The court, in deciding whether to recognise an offence of, say, inciting
the possession of knife in public has no clear answer available to it.
This is in contrast to where the question is recognising attempting attempted
murder, a question to which the court has a secure answer based on the illogic
of such an offence. It cannot be said with certainty that in enacting the
possession of a knife in public offence the legislature intended the ancillary
offence of inciting such possession also. Accordingly, the court is left
with strong discretion in deciding whether to recognise the ancillary
offence. This sits uneasily with the constitutional principle that the
Oireachtas has sole law-making power[230] and the democratic principles behind
the argument for codification of criminal law.[231]
2.121
This problem is, however, somewhat alleviated with the completion of a
codified general part. A prominent general part outlining, among other
things, the scope for relational inchoate offences to attach to special part
offences will raise awareness of this practice. Accordingly, it could be
stated more confidently that the Oireachtas in enacting any particular offence
intends its ancillary inchoate offences also and that, if it wishes to rule
this out, it must do so expressly.
2.122
Is there a criminal attempt in Ireland where the target offence would be
committed outside the jurisdiction? And what about an attempt-act abroad
towards a target offence in Ireland? Bearing in mind the need for the
attempt-act to be sufficiently proximate to the completion of the target
offence, there is limited guidance from case law.[232]
2.123
In Victoria, Australia the Crimes Act 1958[233] provides that an attempt inside the
State to commit an indictable offence outside the State is triable in Victoria,
as is an attempt outside the State to commit an indictable offence within the
State. This provides a model for what statute can say about jurisdiction
for attempts. This model’s assertion in claiming jurisdiction is
consistent with recent statutory development in Ireland about jurisdiction for
conspiracy to commit a serious offence.[234] It is worthwhile to have the
jurisdictional rules consistent for the three general inchoate offences of
attempt, conspiracy and incitement since the same considerations apply to all
three.
2.124
The Commission provisionally recommends that intra-jurisdictional
attempts be expressly recognised as attempts triable within the jurisdiction.
2.125
Some code provisions on attempt as a relational offence expressly
stipulate which categories of crime it is criminal to attempt. The Criminal
Attempts Act 1981 of England and Wales provides that the target of a
criminal attempt must be triable in England and Wales as an indictable offence
and expressly excludes some categories.[235]
2.126
It is apparent that if the provisions on attempt as a relational offence
in the general part of a criminal code are to be comprehensive[236]
then the target of a criminal attempt must be specified. The Criminal
Attempts Act 1981 of England and Wales provides a model for this. The
general part provision on attempt, after providing it is an attempt to commit
an offence, could say that this applies to any offence which, if it were
completed, would be triable in Ireland as an indictable offence.
2.127
There is a question whether this should be limited to indictable
offences. Perhaps not much turns on this question given that only a
minority of special part offences are exclusively summary offences.
Summary offences are still offences and as such the rationale of relational
inchoate offences applies. In any event, a code provision on attempt
should make certain the matter.
2.128
The Commission invites submissions on whether both indictable and
summary offences should be capable of being criminally attempted.
2.129
Is it, and should it be,
criminal to attempt the impossible? As a matter of description of what
the common law is, there is no simple answer. Sometimes at common law
impossibility has been held to bar attempt liability,[237] sometimes not.[238] Types of impossibility need to be
differentiated and defined in order to identify patterns in the case law.
Some judges and writers have used a dual classification of factual and
legal impossibility; some have insisted on greater differentiation within these
categories.[239]
The adjectives “legal” and “factual” are unhelpful because either label
could be applied to a case of impossibility depending on which way it is looked
at.[240]
Consider the famous case of Haughton v Smith.[241] The defendant received what he
believed was “stolen” corned beef. But the corned beef was actually under
the control of the police. The police had searched the van transporting
the corned beef and then allowed the van to continue its journey under covert
police supervision. So Haughton is described as a case of factual
impossibility – the defendant could not have committed the substantive offence
of receiving/handling stolen goods in the circumstances because the goods he
received were not in fact stolen. But the state of being “stolen” is a construct
of the law. Nothing intrinsic to the corned beef changed when the police
discovered it; yet in the view of the law the corned beef changed from being
“stolen” to “not stolen”. Additionally, it is a matter of law that the
goods in question must be “stolen” for the purpose of establishing the offence
of handling stolen goods. It is easy to imagine a different legal regime
where stolen goods are considered stolen until returned to their true owner.
With these rather obvious and uncontroversial observations in mind one
could comfortably describe Haughton as a case of legal impossibility: it
was impossible for the defendant to commit the substantive offence of handling
stolen goods in the circumstances because the law is such that receiving or
handling goods that are under control of the police does not constitute the
offence.
2.130
Instead of “factual” and “legal”, more elucidating phrases can be used
when categorising impossible attempts. So what it often called a case of
legal impossibility can be called a case of an “imaginary crime”. This is
where a person attempts to do, or in fact does, something which they think is
criminal, but is actually not criminal. R v Taafe[242] is an example. The defendant
brought sealed packages into England believing them to contain currency and
believing that importing currency was a crime. As a matter of law,
importing currency is not, and was not, a crime. The English Court of
Appeal held that no criminal attempt was made out because one cannot criminally
attempt to do what is not criminal; where an imaginary crime is attempted the
definition of a criminal attempt will not be satisfied. The imaginary
crime case is best viewed not as a case of impossibility at all, but rather
simply as a case where the definition of attempt – which requires the target of
an attempt to be criminal – is not made out.
2.131
The “factual” impossibility label is applied to the situation where the
accused attempts to do something, which is indeed a crime, but because of facts
unknown to them, cannot possibly be achieved. A classic example is the
“missing booty” case where the defendant tries to pickpocket an empty pocket.
It is impossible to commit theft in this situation, but the actor does
not know this. In R v Brown[243] and R v Ring[244] pick-pocketing an empty pocket was held
to be an attempt to steal. But earlier, in R v Collins,[245]
the opposite was held.[246]
2.132
Another type of case is the “insufficient means” case, a central example
is where a would-be burglar is caught trying to pry open a window with a jemmy
that is entirely inadequate for the job. The House of Lords suggested, obiter,
in Haughton v Smith[247]
that a criminal attempt can be made out here. In R v Whyte[248]
a conviction for attempted murder was upheld where the defendant, intending to
kill, had put poison in the victim’s drink, but the quantity of the particular
poison was inadequate to cause death. This case supports the proposition
that impossibility due to insufficiency of means does not preclude attempt
liability.
2.133
Another type of case is the “mistaken identity” case. An example
is where a person shoots at a tree or a scare-crow mistaking it for someone he
intends to shoot dead. The much cited example of the man who takes his
own umbrella, thinking it belongs to another, fits this category.[249]
2.134
No Irish case on attempt turns on the issue of impossibility, but there
is dictum suggesting impossibility is no defence to a charge of attempt.
In finding that the submission of fictitious birth reports in Sullivan
was capable of constituting an attempt, Walsh J stated that his finding would
be no different even if it was impossible for Sullivan to have passed the 25
birth report mark in the relevant contract year.[250] That is, even if it was
impossible in the circumstances for Sullivan to obtain money by false pretences
she could still be convicted for attempting to do so. It is difficult to
classify the Sullivan case as a type of impossibility because no
particular reason why there might be impossibility was suggested.
2.135
Perhaps Walsh J, when imagining impossibility in Sullivan, had
something in mind along the lines that Sullivan’s false reports would
inevitably be discovered before she could receive extra pay. If this is
so the American case of State v Henthorn[251] has some parallels. The defendant
had written into her doctor’s prescription for codeine, a controlled drug, an
extra “1” thus turning a refill of “1” into “11”. The pharmacist gave the
defendant her first prescription and contacted the police since he knew that a
codeine prescription could be legally refilled at most five times in six
months. On appeal the defendant’s conviction for attempted fraudulent
acquisition of a controlled substance was overturned. The defendant’s
effort at fraud was a hopeless one in the circumstances. Perhaps Walsh J
in Sullivan wished to rule out the possibility of acquittal on such
grounds.
2.136
Proposals and arguments about impossible attempts tend to be made from
two opposing perspectives. Subjectivism recommends the accused be treated
on the basis of circumstances as he or she believed them to be. This
approach treats bludgeoning a dead body with belief it is alive as attempted
murder.[252]
This approach can be called “fault-centred”.[253] In contrast, objectivism can be
called “act-centred”. This approach recommends that bludgeoning a dead
body is not attempted murder no matter what the actor believes because it is
simply not possible to commit murder on a dead body.
2.137
In England and Wales, the Criminal Attempts Act 1981 favours the
subjectivist approach and thus criminalises impossible attempts. S. 1(2)
provides “A person may be guilty of attempting to commit an offence … even
though the facts are such that the commission of the offence is impossible.”
Additionally, section 1(3) provides for attempt mens rea to be
attributed to the accused who would be considered to have the requisite intent
if the facts of the case had been as the accused believed them to be.
2.138
Despite the clear subjectivist principles of the 1981 Act, the House of
Lords in Anderton v Ryan[254]
reached an objectivist result. One year later the Lords did an
about-turn, overruling Anderton v Ryan in the case of R v Shivpuri.[255]
In Anderton v Ryan, Ryan was the victim of a burglary. When
describing what was taken from her home she confessed to a police officer that
her video recorder “was a stolen one” though she could not be sure it was
stolen.[256]
The prosecution, having adduced no evidence that the particular video
recorder was actually stolen, concentrated on a charge of attempted handling of
stolen property. The House of Lords considered whether section 1(3) of
the 1981 Act compelled a court to recognise attempt convictions based on the
defendant’s erroneous view of fact that, if correct, would mean he or she had
committed an offence. A majority of the Court concluded that the statute
did not compel this result. If it did, according to Lord Roskill, the
results would be remarkable. For example, a man who has sex with a woman
of age believing, in error, she is underage would be guilty of attempted unlawful
carnal knowledge. According to Lord Roskill, the legislature would have
to use more “drastic” language than it did in the 1981 Act to enact this.[257]
2.139
In Shivpuri the defendant admitted to customs officials that he
was carrying a suitcase containing prohibited drugs. In fact, the
substance in his case was not a prohibited drug. The House of Lords,
overruling Anderton, held that a conviction for attempting to be
knowingly concerned in dealing with a prohibited drug could stand. Lord
Halisham, obiter, hinted that Shivpuri could have been
distinguished on the facts from Anderton. Ryan’s intention was to
buy a video recorder cheaply; it was not her intention to buy a stolen machine.[258]
This sits uneasily with the legal meaning of intention, which includes
oblique intention. Besides, it could be said of Shivpuri that he intended
to make some money, not to transport drugs.
2.140
The subjectivist approach has been said to lead to punishing people for
their wicked intentions alone because it jettisons the requirement for an actus
reus. In Haughton v Smith[259] Lord Morris said that “to convict [the
defendant] of attempting to handle stolen goods would be to convict him not for
what he did but simply because he had a guilty intention.”[260] There are compelling reasons
against a law that punishes on the basis of yet-to-be-acted-upon guilty
intentions. But this criticism simply does not apply to the subjectivist
approach to impossibility. The defendant in a Shivpuri type case
does not have a mere wicked intention; he has the intention plus he acts on it.
Shivpuri himself did in fact transport a case. From his own point
of view he is doing the actus reus of the offence, which here is the
carrying of a prohibited substance. Furthermore, what he has done must
satisfy the test for the actus reus for attempt, for example, he must
have done a “more than merely preparatory” act.
2.141
Nonetheless, there is a concern that the subjectivist approach to
impossible attempts casts the criminal net too widely. In reality, the
man who steals his own umbrella thinking it belongs to someone else will not
come to the attention of police.[261] The subjectivist approach may go
too far in principle regarding what it catches as criminal.
2.142
In both Shivpuri (transporting a suitcase from India to England
for a large sum of money) and Anderton v Ryan (buying a video recorder
at a very cheap price) the defendants’ false beliefs about that what they were
doing were nonetheless plausible in the circumstances. As such, what
these people did risked substantive criminal harm, the relevant criminal harm
here being the distribution of prohibited drugs (Shivpuri) and the
contribution to the market in stolen goods (Anderton v Ryan). On
another day, Shivpuri might well have been given real drugs to transport;
Ryan’s video recorder might well have been stolen, but could not be considered
so in a criminal court since the prosecution had not sought to prove it.
The rationale of inchoate offences – that of preventing criminal harm and
achieving consistent moral punishment – calls for criminalising the actions of
Ryan and of Shivpuri.
2.143
What about where the defendant’s belief that they are doing something
criminal is not just erroneous in the circumstances, but also entirely
implausible? Consider the person who sticks pins in a doll of likeness to
their enemy[262]
in the belief it will cause injury – must the subjectivist approach label this
a criminal attempt, or is there scope for distinguishing between plausible
beliefs? This Voodoo practitioner poses little threat to society; they do
not in any way increase the risk of criminal harm occurring. To ask the
question more generally, what limits should be placed on the scope for persons
to inculpate themselves through their beliefs under a subjectivist approach?
2.144
The objectivist approach does not accord with the ordinary meaning of
attempt. In ordinary description someone trying to take money from an
empty pocket is attempting to steal just as if the pocket contained money.
The failure to correspond to ordinary language is a disadvantage because
it may hinder the pursuit of legality. The more accurately the law is
understood, the easier it is to obey it.
2.145
Another problem with the objectivist approach is that the more robust it
is, the more it undermines the rationale of inchoate offences. The goals
of preventing criminal harm and applying consistent punishment are undermined
if a conviction cannot be achieved in a Haughton v Smith type of
case. Antony Duff argues that his objectivist framework for attempts
would accommodate conviction in the Haughton v Smith case, though it may
be doubted whether he retains theoretical consistency in doing so. The
objectivist Article 49 of the Italian Penal Code provides that liability shall
be precluded when, owing to the lack of fitness of the action or non-existence
of its object, the harmful or dangerous event is impossible.[263] This has been interpreted so that
conviction is achieved in “empty pocket” type cases. Again, it may be
questioned whether this practice in Italian courts is consistent with the
objectivist text of Article 49.
2.146
The subjectivist approach
is more consistent with the notion of attempt than the objectivist approach.
To say someone attempted something is to make an evaluation of what that
person thought they were doing, not what they actually did. Attempts are
subjective. The debates and problems with impossibility can be seen as
arising from a failure to appreciate this key insight.
2.147
A distinction between
“what is attempted” and “what is done in an attempt” helps resolve much of the
difficulty with so-called impossible attempts.[264] “What is attempted” is what the
actor was attempting to do and this is what the law on criminal attempt is
concerned with. “What is done in an attempt”, on the other hand, is what
has happened from an objective point of view. “What is attempted” should
not be equated with “what is done in an attempt”. They are different
things. Of course, a criminal trial is a very limited format for
assessing subjective perspectives. It is commonplace for subjective
states of mind to be inferred from objective facts. The fact that a man
carried away his own umbrella does not imply he attempted to steal an umbrella,
though he may have had this intention. Additional evidence – perhaps a
confession he believed he was taking someone else’s umbrella – changes the
scenario by providing an insight into his state of mind which may well persuade
us that he was trying to steal an umbrella (what is attempted) rather than
merely carrying away his own umbrella (what is done in an attempt). This
distinction is used by Bebhinn Donnelly to reach the key conclusion that “[an
actor’s] attempt is fixed by [that actor], what actually happens in the attempt
or indeed contrary interpretations of what it is that [the actor is] attempting
cannot retrospectively alter its substance.”
2.148
Another key advance in
theorising about impossible attempts is to recognise the unhelpful nature of
the concept of impossibility.[265] In a very real sense all
attempts, looking back on them, were impossible attempts. Where an actor
has shot at another and the bullet has missed by a matter of inches we can say
that in the circumstances (the gun aimed slightly askew) it was impossible to
commit murder. Impossibility does not differentiate which attempts are
criminal and which are not because it is present in them all.
Additionally, the phrase “attempting the impossible” does not make sense since
by definition an actor who attempts something believes it is possible,
otherwise there would be no point in attempting it and to do so would be
irrational. Of course, we can think of examples where somebody tries to
do something believing it is impossible. This may be rational: an author
trying to write 10,000 words in a day in the hope that reaching for beyond
their capacity will help them achieve their capacity. We can question
whether such a person is really attempting to write 10,000 words; perhaps in
truth they are attempting to write as many words as they can.
2.149
As for the problem of
the subjectivist approach leading to criminalisation of the (seemingly)
harmless voodoo practitioner and other hopelessly inept attempts, this problem
should not be thought fatal for the subjectivist approach because these kinds
of cases are wholly exceptional. They are unlikely to be detected, and
given the requirement of mens rea, the voodoo practitioner would have to
really believe in the efficacy of voodoo.[266] Such an actor might be most
appropriately processed as criminal but excused on the basis of extreme
irrationality or insanity. Perhaps criminalisation is appropriate since
the voodoo practitioner might turn to more effective methods on realising
voodoo doesn’t work.[267]
Such aberrant cases should not be allowed to distort and unduly
complicate attempt liability.
2.150
The Commission
accordingly provisionally favours defining criminal attempt such that it can
label as criminal the person who pick-pockets an empty pocket, the person who
receives non-stolen goods believing them to be stolen, and the person who
despite their best efforts beyond mere preparation simply lacks the means to
achieve their criminal purpose. The only category of attempt
traditionally included under discussion of impossible attempts for which the
Commission provisionally recommends liability should not attach is the
imaginary crime scenario. But in this scenario the concept of impossibility
does not do the work in rendering the action outside the scope of attempt
liability. What renders it outside the scope of attempt liability is the
absence of an essential aspect of a criminal attempt: that the target of the
attempt is an actual currently valid special part offence.
2.151
Though the position in
Ireland on impossible attempts cannot be stated with certainty, most likely it
is the same subjectivist approach that the Commission wishes to provisionally
recommend.[268]
Another way of expressing this position is to observe that impossibility
is no defence.
2.152
The Commission
provisionally recommends that impossibility should not bar attempt liability.
2.153
Abandonment or withdrawal in the context of attempt liability refers to
where the actor wilfully discontinues his or her efforts to bring about a crime,
in other words, where an actor ceases a criminal attempt. The common law
approach is that abandonment has no relevance to the issue of attempt liability
– the attempt is either committed by the time of the abandonment or it is
not. In R v Taylor[269]
the jury acquitted the defendant on facts that had him poised to drop a lighted
match on a haystack. The appeal court allowed this acquittal to stand on
the understanding that the defendant was acquitted for lack of mens rea
– he did not really intend to light the hay, just to make it look like he would
– rather than because he had abandoned a criminal attempt.
2.154
In R v Lankford[270]
the English Court of Criminal Appeal stated:
“In some cases it would be open to the jury to find that a
voluntary change of heart at some point in the proceedings enabled them to say
that there had been no attempt; in other cases a point might be reached where,
even if a man voluntarily desisted, he had already been guilty of the
attempt. Much, of course, depended on the degree of proximity of the acts
in question.”
The first half of this dictum if taken in isolation might
be understood as suggesting a defence of abandonment. Really, it is just
restating the basic actus reus requirement that the defendant progress
beyond preparation and into the realm of attempt.[271] It would, however, be possible to
argue on behalf of a defendant that evidence of subsequent abandonment casts
doubt on whether he had the requisite intention to complete the crime in the
first place.[272]
In the Canadian case of Frankland[273] the fact that the accused had ceased
his efforts to have sex with a non-consenting girl when she started to cry was
considered relevant to the issue of attempt liability not because abandonment
would preclude liability, but because it tended to raise doubt that the defendant
intended non-consensual sex. The Ontario Court of Appeal thought
the jury should have been given direction to consider whether the girl’s crying
signalled to the accused her non-consent and this caused him to stop as it had
never been his intention to have non-consensual sex.
2.155
Canada,[274]
Australia,[275]
and England[276]
take the common law approach for attempt and the other relational inchoate
offences. In The People (Attorney General) v Sullivan Walsh J
confirmed, obiter, that Ireland takes the common law approach in
relation to attempts. The finding that the defendant’s submission of
fictitious births was capable of constituting a criminal attempt would be no
different, in the view of the Supreme Court, if the defendant had abandoned her
quest to gain money for work she had not done.[277]
2.156
In contrast to the common law approach,
the American Law Institute’s Model Penal Code provides for each of the three
inchoate offences an affirmative defence of renunciation of criminal purpose.[278]
Mere voluntary renunciation of criminal purpose suffices as a defence to
attempt. American courts’ interpretation of the common law had tended to
recognise the defence even before codification.[279] The German Penal Code recognises
a general defence of abandonment, which can be made out by preventing the
completion of the target criminal activity.[280] A number of other jurisdictions
have some version of the defence.[281] The Italian Penal Code, unusually
for a civil law jurisdiction, does not recognise abandonment as a defence to
attempt liability. Voluntarily preventing the target offence can,
however, result in a one third to one half reduction in punishment for attempt.[282]
2.157
There are a number of arguments in favour of having an abandonment
defence.
i)
When the law allows for someone to escape attempt liability because they
voluntarily desisted, it respects citizens as responsible agents who are open
to persuasion to desist from their would-be criminal endeavours.[283]
This could be called an argument from moral autonomy. This argument
might be thought to lack appreciation of the reality of
attempting crime. That is, those who attempt crime have already
made their choice about what they want to do. We respect people by
ensuring their freedom to desist from crime; we do not have to additionally
ensure freedom for those who voluntarily try to commit crime to subsequently
turn back at any and all points of their specific criminal endeavour.
ii)
Having an abandonment defence gives the would-be criminal working
towards a crime a prudential reason or motive to desist from completing that
crime. This, it might be supposed, would result in a number of what
otherwise would have been completed crimes being abandoned and hence less
criminal harm than if there was no such defence. A weakness of this
argument is that it is speculative, and perhaps unrealistic,[284] to suppose that would-be criminals
weigh up the pros and cons of continuing their efforts towards crime right up to
the final moment, and even if they do, that the defence of abandonment could
have much impact, given that there is always strong reason to desist since
uncompleted crimes are much less detected than completed crimes.[285]
In addition, if an abandonment defence provides a real incentive to
desist an embarked-on crime it also provides a real, albeit less powerful,
incentive to embark on crime in the first place since it makes embarking on
crime not the “fatal” decision it otherwise is from the point of view of an
actor crossing into the area of criminal liability. In other words, with
an abandonment offence the actor lacks an incentive to refrain from working
towards crime – that once he crosses the threshold of attempt there is, in
theory, no escaping criminal liability – that he has when there is no
abandonment defence.[286]
2.158
Arguments against having a defence of abandonment include:
i)
Once a criminal attempt, which is a complete offence in itself, is made
out why should liability further depend on the particular reason why the target
offence of the attempt was not completed? In criminal law generally,
subsequent regret or remorse does not alter liability. Giving back stolen
money does not alter liability for theft, for example. (Such behaviour
may have relevance to legal issues other than liability, sentencing being the
chief example.) This is logical: we cannot change the past, yet the
defence of abandonment, in effect, allows what was in law a criminal attempt at
one point in time to be changed to not-a-criminal attempt at a time in the
future.[287]
This can be called the argument from logic. The Law Commission for
England and Wales has stated that “[t]he availability of the defence would be
logically indefensible.”[288]
A major problem for this argument is that it could be deflected by
redefining criminal attempt so that an attempt is not made out in the first
place if it was abandoned voluntarily. In other words, build in a
non-abandonment requirement into the definition of attempt. For example,
attempt is committed where an actor “does any act toward the commission of [a]
crime, but fails or is prevented or intercepted in the perpetration thereof”.[289]
The French Penal Code’s definition of attempt would achieve this
effect. Article 121-5, translated: “An attempt is committed where, being
demonstrated by a beginning of execution, it was suspended or failed to achieve
the desired effect solely through circumstances independent of the
perpetrator’s will.” (Emphasis added) This definition implies that if
the attempt fails because of reasons dependent or connected with the
perpetrator’s will then the definition of attempt is not satisfied.
ii)
Some abandoned attempts still cause great “harm”. For example, the
would-be rapist who discontinues his efforts at the last minute may still have
caused immense fear and anxiety.[290] Of course, depending on the facts
there are other offences available to charge, aggravated sexual assault for
example. But what the would-be rapist did is properly labelled attempted
rape rather than some degree of sexual assault. This could be called an
argument from fair labelling.
2.159
If a defence of abandonment is thought desirable it remains to be worked
out when it should be available. A requirement that the abandonment be
voluntary almost goes without saying, for to recognise involuntary abandonment
also would contract criminal attempt so much as to effectively abolish
it. Where the defence is available the meaning of voluntary is more
restricted than the ordinary meaning of the word. To be a voluntary
abandonment in law the defendant must have ceased his work towards substantive crime
for reasons such as:
i)
The would-be perpetrator had a change of heart; he or she decides to
discontinue for moral reasons.
ii)
The would-be perpetrator decides prudentially to obey the law.
That is, they decide, all things considered, they will be better off if they do
not break the law.
2.160
In contrast, the following reasons, though in some sense acted on
“voluntarily”, are not recognised as being sufficient for voluntary
abandonment:
i)
The would-be perpetrator is faced with a very high probability of
getting “caught” whether by law enforcement officers or otherwise.
Section 5.01(4) MPC: “Renunciation of criminal purpose is not voluntary if it
is motivated, in whole or in part, by circumstances, not present or apparent at
the inception of the actor’s course of conduct, that increase the probability
of detection or apprehension or that make more difficult the accomplishment of
the criminal purpose.”
ii)
The would-be perpetrator realises their pursuit of a substantive offence
will not give them the satisfaction they seek. This should be wide enough
to encompass the person who desists because he realises he will not be able to
achieve what he is trying to do.[291]
iii)
The completion of the substantive offence is merely postponed.
Section 5.01(4) MPC: “Renunciation is not complete if it is motivated by a
decision to postpone the criminal conduct until a more advantageous time or to
transfer the criminal effort to another but similar objective or victim.”
Nevertheless, there is a German case[292] where the defence was held available to
a defendant who had desisted from raping on a promise of consensual sex at a
later point.
2.161
Even if, in principle,
the arguments in favour of having a defence of abandonment outweigh those
against, putting the defence in place poses further difficulties:
i)
What type of reverse
onus, if any, to place on the accused?
ii)
Specifying what is
voluntary.
2.162
In light of these
difficulties the French model for defining attempt, which builds the absence of
abandonment by the actor into the positive definition of attempt, is of
interest. The French approach does not require procedural departure from
the presumption of innocence entailed by a reverse onus and it avoids the
problem of deciding what is voluntary by focusing analysis on the reason why
the attempt failed. Only if the reason is independent of the actor’s will
can attempt liability attach. However, opting for this mode of definition
sets up a much less restrictive regime in terms of the potential for
abandonment to render an actor free of attempt liability than does the regime
under the MPC. Given that Ireland currently has the common law position
that abandonment is irrelevant to attempt liability it might be thought that
going for the approach in the French Penal Code would be too dramatic a change.
2.163
The Commission
invites submissions on whether abandonment should have relevance to attempt
liability.
3
3.01
A conspiracy is a criminal agreement. At common law, an agreement
may ultimately have a lawful objective and yet be a criminal conspiracy.[293]
This is apparent in Lord Denman’s definition of conspiracy as agreement
“to do an unlawful act, or a lawful act by unlawful means.”[294] This definition of conspiracy has
been applied by Irish courts on a number of occasions.[295] It is key to note that “unlawful”
in this context does not equate with “criminal”. An agreement to commit a
tort, for example, may be a conspiracy because tortious conduct, though not
criminal, may satisfy the unlawfulness aspect of conspiracy.[296]
3.02
The focus of this
Chapter is the inchoate
offence of conspiracy that attaches to substantive offences and to some
instances of unlawful behaviour. This offence of conspiracy may be called
relational conspiracy or general conspiracy. There are also a number of
specific conspiracy offences identified by judges as existing at common
law. Conspiracy
to defraud and conspiracy to corrupt public morals are prominent examples. These specific conspiracies differ from
relational conspiracy in that they are free-standing offences that have their
target (of the agreement) stipulated, albeit rather vaguely. Discussion
and judgments on these specific conspiracies are, however, very relevant to discussion
on general conspiracy because the concept of agreement – the basis of
conspiracy – is essentially the same for relational conspiracy as for
free-standing conspiracies. Agreement forms the basis of both the actus
reus and mens rea.[297] Agreement is necessarily a mental
operation and thus constitutes the mens rea, yet agreement – the act of
agreement – is the actus reus
3.03
Section 71 of the Criminal Justice Act 2006 contains an offence
of conspiracy. It is limited to persons who conspire to commit a serious
offence. Serious offence is defined as an offence for which a punishment
of four or more years’ imprisonment may be imposed.[298] In this respect, the section 71
offence is much more restricted than common law relational conspiracy in terms
of what it can attach to. The 2006 Act does not, however, state that the
common law relational offence is being replaced. Neither does the statute
define “conspires”.
3.04
The 2006 Act stipulates jurisdictional claims such that the target of a
section 71 conspiracy formed in Ireland can be an offence to be committed
outside of the jurisdiction provided it constitutes a serious offence in the
country where it will occur and if done in Ireland would be a serious
offence. Section 71 also claims jurisdiction over conspiracy formed
abroad where the target offence is to be committed in Ireland or to be
committed abroad if against an Irish citizen or stateless person normally
resident in Ireland.
3.05
Conspiracy in Ireland is still very much a matter of common law.
In late 2007 the alleged actors in a foiled raid attempt in Celbridge, Co.
Kildare were charged with conspiracy to commit theft contrary to common law.[299]
Section 71 can be seen as a codification of that subset of common law
relational conspiracy that is committed where a serious offence, as
distinguished from minor offences and non-criminal wrongs, is agreed to be
pursued as an end or as a means. The 2006 Act gives detailed guidance on
jurisdictional issues of law that are uncertain at common law, but this applies
to section 71 conspiracy, not to conspiracy generally. Significantly, the
absence of any definition of conspiracy in the 2006 Act means that even where a
trial falls under the ambit of section 71, recourse to common law will be
required.
3.06
Agreement for the purpose of conspiracy has its ordinary meaning; it is
an act of communication – or tacit understanding – between two or more persons
involving resolution to do something. This process might involve an
express exchange of promises, but need not. Case law indicates that
agreement in conspiracy need not amount to what is needed for a binding
contract in contract law.[300]
But at least one authority implies that a conspiratorial agreement is
such that it would be an enforceable contract if lawful.[301] Yet the courts have not insisted
there be consideration present for conspiratorial agreements, nor have they
analysed such agreements in terms of offer and acceptance.[302] The conspirator merely needs to
be a party to the agreement; she does not have to be involved in the “making”
of it.[303]
So long as the agreement exists – that is, until it is carried out or
abandoned – the offence of conspiracy is being committed. It is a
continuing offence.[304]
3.07
The concept of
agreement in conspiracy is one of the less controversial aspects of conspiracy.
Codification would involve providing that conspiring is an act of agreement
where agreement has its ordinary meaning rather than a technical meaning as in
the law of contracts.
3.08
The Commission
provisionally recommends that conspiracy continue to be based on the concept of
agreement, which should have its ordinary meaning.
3.09
There are further
issues arising with the actus reus of conspiracy, which are addressed
presently.
3.10
It is obvious that at least two people are needed for a conspiratorial
agreement. However, in practice in Ireland and elsewhere it is possible
to convict only one person for a particular conspiracy. The Court of
Criminal Appeal in The People (Attorney General v Keane) held that the
deletion of the name of an alleged co-conspirator from a charge does not affect
a conviction.[305]
In line with this
position, there is a practice whereby a charge of conspiracy does not have to
name the party with whom the accused is alleged to have conspired; the
indictment can allege a conspiracy with “a person or persons unknown.”[306]
Where two defendants are tried
together for the same alleged conspiracy, common law holds that the acquittal
of one requires the acquittal of the other.[307] This
was how the English courts applied the
common law[308] up to the enactment of section 5 of the Criminal Law Act
1977,
which reversed the rule. In a
contrasting application of the common law, the High Court of Australia held in R
v Darby[309]
that, whether tried separately or jointly, the
acquittal of one co-conspirator does
not necessitate the other’s acquittal. It is less than certain what the
position is in Ireland, though a recommended practice would be to have separate
trials for co-conspirators where the evidence against one is stronger than
against the other because, for example, one has made an admission. A
guilty plea by one party to a conspiracy charge should not prejudice the trial
of another party.[310]
Nor can the confession of one party be used against another.
However, the declaration of one party in furtherance of the alleged conspiracy
is admissible evidence against all parties insofar as it establishes the
existence of the conspiracy. This is a recognised exception to the
hearsay rule; it applies only after the prosecution have already made out a prima
facie case of conspiracy. It is also observed that declarations made
after arrest would not be admissible under this rule because they could not, at
that stage, be in furtherance of the conspiracy.[311]
3.11
That more than one person happen to share the same intention to do the
same unlawful thing is not sufficient for a conspiracy - “[a] conspiracy
consists not merely in the intention of two or more but the agreement of two or
more …”[312]
That is not to say that there must be direct evidence of a verbal or
written exchange revealing the existence and content of agreement between
conspirators. The Court of Criminal Appeal in The People (Attorney
General) v O’Connor and O’Reilly[313] held that, in the absence of evidence
of an express agreement, its existence can be inferred from evidence supporting
other charges against the accused. The other charges in this case were
offences of breaching Emergency Orders regulating the sale of certain
commodities. These offences were the substantive offences that the
defendants were accused of conspiring to commit.
3.12
The People (Attorney General) v Keane[314] illustrates how an agreement can be
inferred from evidence of activity that has the appearance of being done
pursuant to agreed actions. Keane concerned prosecutions for
conspiracy to cause explosions.[315] There was no direct evidence of
an agreement between the alleged conspirators. But there was a notebook
in the defendant’s (Keane’s) handwriting containing diagrams and notes for
making explosives; Keane’s finger-prints were on a box containing a bomb timing
device found in the lock-up garage of a co-conspirator named Murray; and at the
premises of another co-conspirator named Longmore there was found an
explosives-making manual and a time-table with Keane’s finger-print on
it. Walsh J in the Court of Criminal Appeal sums up the trial court’s
conclusion:
“On this evidence the Court was satisfied that there was
clearly an association between the parties concerned … and that it related to
the making of explosive devices and that the object of making these explosive
devices was to cause explosions within the State.”[316]
Walsh J, in affirming the defendant’s conviction, went on to
say that there was sufficient evidence on which to find the defendant conspired
to cause explosions with Murray, but not with Longmore.
3.13
The Court of Criminal
Appeal’s holding in O’Connor and O’Reilly[317] and in Keane[318] is consistent with the common law
practice as revealed in the English cases and described by Dennis: “the
existence of the agreement is invariably inferred from overt acts apparently
performed pursuant to the agreement.”[319]
3.14
Walsh J in The People (Attorney General) v Keane[320]
stated it was not necessary for co-conspirators to have met in person in order
for a conspiratorial agreement to be found.[321] This opinion accords with 19th Century common law
authorities,[322]
which were endorsed by the Supreme
Court in Attorney General v Oldridge.[323] Keane CJ speaking for the Court
quoted the following passage of Coleridge J’s judgment in
R v Murphy with approval:
“It is not necessary that it should be proved that these
defendants met to concoct this scheme, nor is it necessary that they should
have originated it. If a conspiracy be already formed, and a person joins
it afterwards, he is equally guilty.”[324]
3.15
This holding has been affirmed in England[325] and is also consistent with
interpretations of the common law that acknowledge how third parties can act as
a “go between” thus there being no need for conspirators to have directly
communicated with each other. American courts in purporting to apply the
common law recognise “wheel” and “chain” conspiracies.[326] A wheel conspiracy involves a
person in the middle acting as a go-between for a number of different
participants. A chain conspiracy involves actors who may have contact
with only one other participant, but are still part of an overall effort.[327]
3.16
The High Court in Hegarty v Governor of Limerick Prison[328]
indicated that a mere coordination of plans cannot satisfy the agreement
requirement for conspiracy. In that case the DPP became aware that there
was a problem with the lawfulness of the prisoner’s detention. Having
been in communication with the gardaí, the prison authorities released the
prisoner. The prisoner was then immediately re-arrested by the gardaí
outside the prison. Geoghegan J held that there was no conspiracy here
because there was no agreement and, in any event, there was no unlawfulness
element.
3.17
In light of Hegarty Irish law on agreement in conspiracy has
departed slightly from interpretations of common law elsewhere. Dicta
in the Brighton Conspiracy Case[329] states that a “tacit understanding”
between putative conspirators as to what they were to do is sufficient for a
conspiratorial agreement. Such a
“tacit understanding” was apparently present in the reported facts of Hegarty,
yet Geoghegan J said it was not enough to constitute conspiratorial agreement.
3.18
Questions of jurisdiction arise regarding agreements formed in one
country to do something in another county that is unlawful in that other
country.[330]
Section 71 of the Criminal Justice Act 2006 provides that
agreements in Ireland to do serious offences (for which four or more years’
imprisonment can be imposed) abroad is a section 71 conspiracy. Also
constituting section 71 conspiracies are agreements abroad to commit a serious
offence in Ireland, a serious offence against an Irish citizen or resident
abroad, or a serious offence on an Irish ship or aircraft.
3.19
For conspiracies falling outside section 71 there is case law on
jurisdictional matters applying the common law. In R v Doot[331]
the defendants, while outside England, had agreed to import illegal drugs into
England. The House of Lords held that the defendants could be guilty of
conspiracy because it is a continuing offence and there was evidence that the
defendants had come into English territory in order to carry out their
plan. The Supreme Court agreed with this view in Ellis v O’Dea and
Governor of Portlaoise Prison stating:
“It would be the very negation of an adequate criminal
jurisdiction and an absurdity if a person joining in a … conspiracy … could
escape responsibility by reason of the fact that he has committed no overt act
within the jurisdiction.”[332]
3.20
English judgments have gone further, stating that a conspiracy to do
something unlawful within the jurisdiction, though formed abroad, is
justiciable.[333]
And this is so without any of the conspirators having come into the
jurisdiction. This position is effectively what section 71 of the 2006
Act provides for serious offence conspiracies.
3.21
There is also a jurisdictional question about conspiracy formed within
the jurisdiction to do something unlawful abroad. In Board of
Trade v Owen[334] the House of Lords held that a
conviction for conspiracy did not lie in this situation.
3.22
The Canadian Criminal Code provides that it is a conspiracy under
Canadian law to agree abroad to do something in Canada if such agreement would
be a conspiracy if done in Canada[335] and it is also a conspiracy to agree in
Canada to do something abroad that if to be done in Canada would be conspiracy.[336]
3.23
The law on conspiracy
could benefit from having certainty introduced regarding issues of
jurisdiction. Section 71 of the Criminal Justice Act 2006 pursues
this aim, but is confined to a limited class of conspiracy, that where the
target of the agreement is a serious offence. The same jurisdictional
rules could be applied to conspiracy generally.
3.24
The Commission
provisionally recommends that jurisdiction be claimed for cross border
conspiracies generally.
3.25
Agreements between certain persons cannot constitute conspiracies.
Husband and wife cannot conspire together at common law.[337] Charleton, McDermott and Bolger explain
this “spousal immunity” rule as flowing from the law’s view of spouses as a
single entity possessing a single will.[338] There is no recent Irish judicial
pronouncement on this rule. There are, however, a number of legal
developments suggesting that spouses are no longer always in law considered to
be one person. In The State (DPP) v Walsh[339]
Henchy J explained the common law defence of marital coercion:
“In an effort to compensate the wife for her inferior status,
and in particular to make up for her inability to plead benefit of clergy, as
her husband could, the law concocted the fiction of a prima facie presumption
that the act done by her in the presence of her husband was done under
coercion.”[340]
Henchy J went on to state, obiter,
that the rule was invalid for inconsistency with the Constitution’s equality
guarantee[341]
due to the rule’s presupposition of a wife’s inferior status.[342]
3.26
In United States v Dege[343]
the US Supreme Court declined to apply the common law rule that spouses cannot
conspire together. The rule was preserved in England and Wales in the Criminal
Law Act 1977,[344]
but the Law Commission for England and Wales has recently called for its
abolition.[345]
3.27
The marital coercion rule necessarily presupposes that a wife has an
inferior status to her husband; the spousal immunity rule does not. The
spousal immunity rule, therefore, does not offend equality to the same extent
as the marital coercion rule.[346] Nevertheless, it is anomalous
that a married couple should be exempt from conspiracy liability. There
seems to be no explanation available beyond the outdated notion of husband and
wife as a single entity. It is not thought that agreements between
spouses to pursue crime was intended to be protected under the constitutional
right to marital privacy recognised in McGee v Attorney General.[347]
The Constitution has been interpreted as requiring a certain amount of
privilege for communications within marriage.[348] This may have implications for
matters of evidence, but does not impact on substantive liability. If
there is an argument that the spousal immunity rule is required by the
constitutional protection of marriage, it will have to address Murray v
Ireland.[349] In Murray v Ireland the Supreme
Court held that the constitutional rights flowing from marriage were suspended
on imprisonment for the commission of crime. This implies that marriage
rights may be limited in order to secure the operation of criminal
justice. Codification presents an opportunity for eliminating uncertainty
about the existence of the spousal immunity rule by expressly abolishing it.
3.28
The Commission provisionally recommends the abolition of the rule
that spouses cannot conspire together.
3.29
The common law provides limited guidance on whether there is a
conspiracy where one of the two parties (assuming a two person conspiracy for
explanatory purposes) is exempt from liability for the target unlawful
act. For example, where a man and an underage girl plan (that is,
conspire) to elope together, the girl cannot be liable for the target offence
of abduction, the man can. The common law is unclear as to the girl’s
potential liability for conspiracy. In R v Whitechurch[350] it was held that a non-pregnant women
(under section 58 of the Offences Against the Person Act 1861 a non-pregnant
women cannot be liable for attempting to procure her own miscarriage) could be
guilty of conspiracy to procure an abortion. This suggests that a person
who cannot be guilty of a target offence can be guilty for conspiring to commit
the target offence.[351]
An important principle that was not applicable in the Whitechurch
case, but would apply in the example of the underage girl eloping, is that
offences which exist for the protection of a certain class of person should not
be applied so as to criminalise that class of
person.[352]
This principle indicates that the girl in the elopement example would not
be liable for conspiring to commit the crime of abduction since the crime of
abduction is there to protect the girl.
3.30
The more important question from a practical point of view is whether
the man in the abduction scenario may be guilty of conspiracy. The answer
at common law is that the man may indeed be guilty of conspiracy. In R
v Duguid[353] the court affirmed the defendant’s
conviction (for conspiracy to take a child aged under 14 years out of the
possession of whoever was legally guarding the child) even though the
defendant’s co-conspirator (the child’s mother) was statutorily immune from
prosecution for this offence.
3.31
The Law Commission for
England and Wales has helpfully distinguished[354] between, on the one hand, the situation
where one party to a conspiracy is exempt from liability (for example, a
defence of duress is available) or is a legally protected person (as in the
elopement example above) and, on the other hand, the situation where one party
to a conspiracy simply lacks criminal capacity (for example, a child below the
age of criminal responsibility). The rule for the first situation is that
liability for conspiracy can attach to the party who is not in the legally
protected class of persons. This restates R v Duguid.[355] The Law Commission for
England and Wales now proposes that all parties here be liable for conspiracy,
but that the persons exempt from liability for the target offence would have a
defence.[356]
3.32
The current rule in
England and Wales[357]
for the second situation above involving the child incapable of crime is that
neither party can be liable for conspiracy. This is rationalised by the
Law Commission for England and Wales as flowing from the fact that conspiracy,
the essence of which is a meeting of minds, cannot exist where only one mind
has the capacity for crime.[358]
Some other offence needs to be relied on to catch the non-morally
innocent party.
3.33
The Commission sees no
need to provisionally recommend other than a rationalisation of what is most
likely the current law in Ireland.
3.34
The Commission
provisionally recommends that conspiracy not be made out where only one party
to it has criminal capacity.
3.35
The Commission
provisionally recommends that exemption from liability for the target offence
of a conspiracy on the part of one or more parties should not cause other
parties to the conspiracy to escape conspiracy liability.
3.36
A conspiracy is an agreement to do something unlawful. The
agreement must be entered intentionally and with knowledge or belief of what
the agreement is about. Furthermore, there must be intention that the
agreement be carried out. Ormerod[359] thus suggests three aspects make up the
mens rea of conspiracy:
i)
Intention to enter the agreement (intention to agree).
ii)
Knowledge or belief of the circumstances of carrying out the agreement
and what the agreement entails (knowledge).
iii)
Intention that the details of the agreement or plan be carried out
(intention to succeed).
3.37
Irish courts have not had occasion to spell out this requirement
expressly. It has been taken as given that conspirators must intend to
agree to the unlawful enterprise. That is, it is not sufficient that they
nod their head at the appropriate time and thus give the outwards appearance of
agreement if they do not truly intend to agree. Here, as in other
respects, agreement in conspiracy differs from agreement in contract law.
The Canadian courts have expressly isolated this aspect of the mental requirements
for conspiracy, saying it is essential for conspiracy that the conspirators
have intention to agree.[360]
3.38
The conspirator does not have to know or believe that what
is being contemplated is actually unlawful or that merely agreeing to it
is criminal since, as ever in criminal law, ignorance of the law is no
excuse. And “[i]t does not matter how prosaic the unlawful act may be or
how ignorant the conspirators may be of the fact that the act is prohibited by
[ ] statutory provision.”[361]
In other words, the knowledge requirement applies to facts (the content
of the agreement and the circumstances in which it is to be carried out), not
law. Complete or extensive knowledge of the details of the plan is not
required to satisfy the knowledge requirement.[362]
3.39
It has been suggested that the conspirator must intend the agreement to
be carried out.[363]
This means that the conspirator must intend that the consequences the
agreement specifies (to be brought about) actually happen, not just that agreement
happens. The House of Lords, interpreting the common law, insisted on
this element in Churchill v Walton.[364] Subsequently, in R v Anderson,[365]
the House of Lords, applying section 1 of the Criminal Law Act 1977,
said it was not necessary for the accused to intend the conspiracy to
ultimately succeed once he had agreed to it. However, courts have not
strictly followed the Anderson approach. R v McPhillips[366] is an example. The defendant was
among a group who planned to explode a bomb at a disco when in full
swing. The Court of Appeal of Northern Ireland held that the defendant
could not be guilty of conspiracy to murder because he – unlike his
co-conspirators – had intended to give a warning call so that the disco would
be evacuated by the time the bomb exploded. It
is noted that McPhilips can be distinguished from Anderson on the
basis that McPhilips should not be guilty of conspiracy due to the fact that he
joined the conspiratorial agreement with the purpose of frustrating it and thus
may qualify for acquittal on public policy grounds.[367]
Nonetheless, the McPhilips decision as well as a number of English Court
of Appeal decisions can be seen, as Ormerod suggests, as judicial discomfort
with the Anderson holding that it is not essential
for the accused to intend the conspiracy succeed in order to be guilty of that
conspiracy.
3.40
In R v Saik[368] Lord Nicholls, speaking for the House
of Lords, described the mens rea of conspiracy as including intention
that the act or acts agreed on be in fact carried out.
3.41
The experience in
England and Wales and Northern Ireland is instructive for Ireland. The Anderson[369] decision is
unsatisfactory and has generated much critical comment;[370] the approach of the House of Lords in Saik[371] is
preferable.
3.42
The Commission
provisionally recommends that the mens rea of conspiracy include a requirement for intention that the
conspiratorial plan actually be carried out.
3.43
A conspiracy is an agreement to do something unlawful or something
lawful by unlawful means. “Unlawful” in this context has a wide
definition; it describes a much wider range of conduct than “criminal”.
3.44
Summary offences, as well as more serious offences, satisfy the
unlawfulness requirement at common law.[372]
3.45
Conspiracy to incite has been recognised in 1999 in England.[373]
In R v James and Ashford[374]
convictions for conspiracy to incite a specific offence were overturned.
The Court stated: “even if it is possible (as it may be) for there to exist a
conspiracy to incite one person to incite ultimate users, that was certainly
neither the thrust nor the factual position proved in the present case.”
Conspiracy to incite has also been recognised in Canada.[375] Conspiracy to attempt has been
recognised in the United States.[376] But it cannot be said that this
is a logically sound crime because if the mens rea of conspiracy is
intention to bring about an unlawful result how can this be satisfied by
intending that an unlawful result is merely attempted? By definition,
intending something to be merely attempted implies the absence of intention
that it be completed. Conspiracy to conspire suffers the same logical
flaw. The mens rea of conspiracy cannot be satisfied by agreeing
to merely conspire as opposed to seeing through the completion of an unlawful
act.
3.46
The concerns expressed in Chapter 2 above[377] about attempt attaching to other
inchoate offences apply with equal force to conspiracy attaching to other
inchoate offences.
3.47
In Parnell’s case[378] it was held that some conduct, merely
tortious when done by a single actor, is a criminal conspiracy when planned or
organised by multiple actors in concert. Kamara v DPP[379]
is a more recent example from England. In this case there was a
conviction for conspiracy to trespass where the trespass in question was a
non-criminal trespass.
3.48
Geoghegan J in Hegarty v Governor of Limerick Prison[380]
left open the question whether there can be a conspiracy to infringe a person’s
constitutional rights. The Hegarty decision was decided on grounds
other than this question. The applicant’s case had failed on at least two
grounds – the need to establish agreement and the need to establish that
carrying out this agreement would breach the applicant’s constitutional rights
– prior to the issue of whether a breach of constitutional rights is unlawful
for the purposes of conspiracy. Hegarty should not be read as
ruling out breach of constitutional rights constituting the unlawfulness aspect
of conspiracy.
3.49
Connelly v Lochney[381] is a conspiracy case from the 1950s
where it was held that an agreement was not a criminal conspiracy because what
was done pursuant to the agreement was neither criminal nor tortious. The
agreement in question was between members of a retailers’ association to refuse
to trade with the complainant for the reason that the complainant was pricing
goods below the association’s agreed minimum retail price. The practice
of the retailers’ association in setting up and attempting to enforce a price
fixing arrangement would be in breach of Irish competition law at present,
though it was not in breach of the relevant trade union law of the day.
3.50
Connelly clearly cannot be taken as authority suggesting breach
of competition law norms does not satisfy the unlawfulness element of
conspiracy. Horizontal price fixing is illegal in Ireland now; it was not
in the 1950s. Hence, what was not a conspiracy in the 1950s could be a
conspiracy now given the development of competition law.
3.51
There is no case law establishing that breach of contract suffices for
the unlawfulness aspect of conspiracy.[382] A number of conspiracy to defraud
cases, however, involve what might be described as agreements to breach
contract.[383]
3.52
There are no cases on whether breaching EU law constitutes the
unlawfulness aspect of conspiracy. The question here is perhaps
misconceived. The EU is a source of law rather than a type of law.
The question to ask in assessing whether conspiracy can attach to any
particular law that comes ultimately from the EU is what type of law it
is? If it is a criminal offence then clearly its breach satisfies the
unlawfulness requirement.
3.53
There are a number of specific common law conspiracy offences.
Conspiracy to defraud is a leading example. These conspiracy offences
differ from conspiracy as a relational offence, the latter being the focus of
this Chapter. Whereas conspiracy as a relational offence attaches to
yet-to-be-identified specific unlawfulness (from the general sphere of
unlawfulness), the specific conspiracies are free-standing and set out in
advance what they attach to, albeit without much precision.
3.54
It is useful, perhaps indispensable, to consider the specific
conspiracies when considering conspiracy as a relational offence because the
concept of agreement is the same for both, and the arguments for and against
restricting conspiracy are applicable to both.
3.55
The Irish superior courts have repeatedly affirmed in recent years the
existence of the common law offence of conspiracy to defraud.[384]
The following definition was endorsed by the High[385] and Supreme Courts:[386]
“[A]n agreement by two or more by dishonesty to deprive a
person of something which is his or to which he is or would be or might be
entitled and an agreement by two or more by dishonesty to injure some
proprietary right of his, suffices to constitute the offence of conspiracy to
defraud.”[387]
3.56
In Myles v Sreenan[388] the High Court rejected an argument
that conspiracy to defraud had not survived, due to vagueness, the enactment of
the Constitution of Ireland.
3.57
In Attorney General (SPUC) v Open Door Counselling Ltd[389]
the High Court was asked to declare that the conduct of the respondent
organisations constituted conspiracy to corrupt public morals. The
organisations gave non-directive counselling to pregnant women and were
prepared to refer such women to abortion-performing clinics in England.
Hamilton P remarked:
“Such an agreement could constitute a conspiracy to corrupt
public morals as the defendants’ services are available to the public and
well-advertised.”
But the Court would not declare that the alleged offence was
being committed, since it was a matter for a jury to decide based on the particular
circumstances of a case.
3.58
In Attorney General (SPUC) v Open Door Counselling Ltd[390]
Hamilton P cited the House of Lords’ decision in Knuller v DPP[391] as “clear authority” that the offence “may be committed even
when the agreement … is to assist in the commission of a lawful act.”[392]
This helps reveal how conspiracy to corrupt public morals is a distinct
free-standing offence and not just an instance of relational conspiracy.
This is because relational conspiracy is restricted to agreements to do
unlawful acts (or lawful acts by unlawful means); there is an essential
“unlawfulness” component. In contrast, what Knuller asserts and
the SPUC case accepts, is that “unlawfulness” is not an essential
component of conspiracy to corrupt public morals.
3.59
The use of “lawful act” in the SPUC case could, however, be read
as merely referring to the fact that the abortion procedures, though criminal
in Ireland, were lawful in England provided certain conditions were met.[393]
But in light of Knuller and its approval in the High Court it is
clear that conspiracy to corrupt public morals really is an offence that is
wider than common law conspiracy as a relational offence. The conduct
considered capable of constituting conspiracy to corrupt public morals in Knuller
was the publishing of information allowing adult male homosexuals to meet for
sex. This publication was produced, and presumably planned, after the
decriminalization in England of sexual acts between adult males. The
following passage of Lord Reid’s judgment in Knuller was quoted
approvingly by Hamilton P in the SPUC case:
“I find nothing in the Act to indicate that Parliament
thought or intended to lay down that indulgence in these practices [sexual acts
between men] is not corrupting. I read the Act [Sexual Offences Act
1967]
as saying that, even though it may be corrupting, if people choose to corrupt
themselves in this way that is their affair and the law will not
interfere. But no licence is given to others to encourage the
practice. So if one accepts Shaw’s case[394] as rightly decided it must be left to
each jury to decide in the circumstances of each case whether people were
likely to be corrupted.”
3.60
So
there is a zone where conduct though not criminal or in breach of any other
area of law is still not to be – if one wishes to avoid being a criminal –
encouraged or facilitated by two or more. How do people know what conduct
is in this twilight zone? The answer of the English and Irish courts:
where a jury would consider that in the circumstances such conduct is
“corrupting”. Case law suggests some qualities that might help pick out
what this is: erstwhile illegality[395] or illegality elsewhere.[396]
3.61
In Knuller[397] the House of Lords inferred from a number of discrete
precedents (keeping a disorderly house, indecent exhibition, and others) the
existence of a general common law offence of outraging public decency, which
has an ancillary inchoate offence of conspiracy to outrage public decency.[398]
Thus conspiracy to outrage public decency is a relational offence, that
is, an inchoate offence parasitic on a substantive offence.
3.62
There does not appear to be any Irish judicial recognition of this
offence. additionally, there would be a question mark over the
constitutionality of an Irish court engaging in a similar enterprise to what
the House of Lords did in Knuller – a process of induction where a
general offence is extracted from a number of specific offences.
3.63
In DPP v Carew[399]
Hamilton J recognised the substantive offence of effecting a public
mischief. Hence, it can be said there is implicit Irish judicial
recognition of conspiracy to effect a public mischief. This is implicit
because the existence of the substantive offence entails the existence of the
ancillary conspiracy offence. There is a House of Lords decision[400]
stating there is no such offence known to the law. This House of Lords
decision predates, but is not mentioned in, Hamilton J’s judgment in Carew.[401]
There are some cases from Australia recognising the offence.[402]
Where it is recognised, public mischief is the substantive offence and
agreeing to pursue it constitutes conspiracy.
3.64
Having surveyed the unlawfulness aspect of relational conspiracy and the
specific common law conspiracy offences the big question is whether, and to
what extent, conspiracy should be reined in? The options include:
i)
Restricting relational conspiracy to agreement to do criminal acts
whether those criminal acts are the goal of the agreement or side effects of
pursuing the agreement’s goal.
ii)
Abolishing the specific common law conspiracies.
3.65
The same motivation drives these two suggestions, that of restricting
conspiracy to those agreements relating to substantive crime. Yet it
would be possible to follow one and not the other. This was done in England
and Wales with the passing of the Criminal Law Act 1977, which
restricted relational conspiracy to agreement relating to crime, yet left
intact the specific common law conspiracies.
3.66
Arguments for restricting conspiracy to agreements relating to crimes
include:
i)
The argument from legality. The legality principle states that
persons should be punished only where their behaviour contravenes a clearly
defined and previously promulgated rule of criminal law. Conspiracy when
not restricted to relating to criminal offences violates this principle because
it is uncertain and open-ended. It is no coincidence that conspiracy has
been associated with the suppression of political campaigns for it provides
courts with a huge area of discretion within which to criminalise conduct that
unsettles the status quo.[403]
ii)
The argument from consistency, where the consistency sought is that
between law as stated and law in action. Like the legality principle this
principle is part of the rule of law ideal. Conspiracy when not
restricted to criminal matters violates this principle because it criminalises
a very wide range of behaviour that is not in reality – and perhaps could never
be – processed through the criminal justice system. In other words,
conspiracy over-criminalises, it over-reaches in its ambition. The
greater the short-fall between what the law indicates to be criminal and what
it processes as criminal the more the rule of law is undermined.
3.67
Arguments for retaining conspiracy as relating to unlawfulness include:
i)
The argument from efficacy. Conspiracy, being wide and flexible,
can be used to catch novel conduct (where more than one person is involved),
which though not previously labelled as criminal may nonetheless be harmful and
immoral.
ii)
The so-called argument from “thin-ice” can be articulated in an effort
to meet the legality argument mentioned above. Lord Morris in Knuller
v DPP[404]
said “those who skate on thin ice can hardly expect to find a sign which will
denote the precise spot where they will fall in.” The ice-skating
metaphor is inapt – and thus makes the argument appear simply unconcerned about
legality – given that there is nothing remotely “bad” about ice-skating.
The basic idea[405]
underlying the argument from thin ice is that when persons do things that are
dishonest or are somewhat like criminal behaviour they cannot legitimately
complain if the criminal justice system subsequently processes them as
criminal.
3.68
When restricting conspiracy it may be thought desirable to not jettison
all conspiracy offences that do not relate to substantive criminal acts.
McAuley and McCutcheon make a case[406] for distinguishing conspiracy to
defraud from the other specific common law conspiracies and indeed from
conspiracy relating to unlawful, but not criminal, acts. First, it is
pointed out that even in jurisdictions that have limited conspiracy to relating
to criminal offences,[407]
the free-standing offence of conspiracy to defraud has been maintained.
Second, the usefulness of the offence historically in addressing gaps in theft
law is demonstrated.[408]
Third, the argument from legality that is used against conspiracy to
defraud is addressed. Unlike conspiracy to corrupt public morals, which
violates the legality principle because there is no common understanding of
what the boundaries of public morals are, with conspiracy to defraud the
examples of dishonesty, deceit, and misrepresentation that make up the fraud
aspect of the offence “might be said to be included in the popular
understanding” of theft.[409]
This point, expressed so tentatively, is difficult to dispute. But
the authors go on to make the point more forcefully:
“Although the definition of conspiracy to defraud is
undoubtedly hydra-headed, its incriminating features have been clearly and
consistently delineated by the courts for at least two centuries. Indeed,
the authorities effectively mark the spots at which the imprudent skater is likely
to come to a watery end. Seen in this light, it is doubtful if the
definition of conspiracy to defraud would fall foul of the rule against
retrospection in Article 15.5 of the Irish Constitution.”[410]
3.69
This view that conspiracy to defraud is consistent with the Constitution
has proved to be an accurate prediction of the High Court’s view.[411]
So too the Supreme Court has expressly endorsed the authors’ assertion
that the offence has some measure of certainty.[412] This does not preclude debate
about reforming or abolishing conspiracy to defraud since it is emphatically
not the case that unconstitutionality is a prerequisite for legislative reform,
nor is it the case that all parts of the quoted passage, though approved of by
the Chief Justice, are beyond dispute.
3.70
In 1973 the Law Commission for England and Wales recommended that the
law should recognise only conspiracies to commit crimes. This
recommendation was enacted in the Criminal Law Act 1977 (UK).
3.71
The Law Commission for England and Wales has examined conspiracy to
defraud on multiple occasions. The Law Commission repeatedly recommended
the offence be preserved, if only as a temporary measure for fear of gaps in
its absence,[413]
before finally in 2002 recommending its abolition.[414]
3.72
The Canadian Criminal Code has been interpreted by the Supreme Court of
Canada as restricting conspiracy to conspiracy relating to statutory offences.[415]
The position in Canada, accordingly, is that the common law specific
conspiracies are abolished.[416]
3.73
Finally, it is noted, for the avoidance of doubt, that conspiracy to
defraud at common law includes agreements to do criminal acts that might be
grouped under the heading “fraud”, for example, counterfeiting and forgery
under the Criminal Justice (Theft and Fraud Offences) Act 2001.
Conspiracy to defraud at common law also includes agreements to do acts which
may not be criminal but which dishonestly cause deprivation or injury to
another’s proprietary right and accordingly satisfy the definition of
conspiracy to defraud.[417]
Abolishing conspiracy to defraud involves abolishing the latter but not the
former category of conspiracy. This is so because conspiracy as a general
relation offence attaching to all offences will still catch the former category
of agreements to do criminal fraudulent acts.
3.74
The arguments in favour
of restricting conspiracy to agreements to do criminal, as opposed to merely
unlawful, things are compelling. As things stand, a non-criminal activity
can be held by the Courts to become criminal when agreed to be done by two or
more actors. This offends the legality principle because there is a lack
of advance notice of what it is criminal to do. It also offends the Irish
Constitution’s democratic principle that the Oireachtas has exclusive
law-making power since it is the courts and not the Oireachtas that decides
which unlawful, though non-criminal, activity it is a conspiracy to agree to
do. For consistency, restricting conspiracy in this way should be
accompanied by an abolition of the specific common law conspiracies. In
this regard, however, special considerations apply to conspiracy to defraud.
3.75
The Commission
provisionally recommends that conspiracy be limited to agreements to do
criminal acts and that the common law offences of conspiracy to corrupt public
morals, to outrage public decency, and to effect a public mischief be
abolished.
3.76
The Commission
invites submissions on whether conspiracy to defraud should be retained.
3.77
An impossible conspiracy describes where there is agreement to do
something unlawful (whether the unlawful thing is an end or a means), but
circumstances are such that it is simply not possible for that particular
unlawful thing to be done.
3.78
There is no Irish case addressing an impossible conspiracy, but there is
English authority on the common law position. In DPP v Nock and
Alsford[418] the House of Lords held that at common
law there was no liability for conspiring to do a specific criminal act that
was in the circumstances impossible. In Nock the defendants
admitted that they intended to extract cocaine from a white powder in their
possession. The white powder, contrary to the defendants’ belief, could
never yield cocaine. The House of Lords held that, because the agreement
was specific to extracting cocaine from the particular batch of white powder,
the defendants could not be convicted. Lord Scarman stated obiter
that had the agreement been more general – for example, an agreement to enter
into a general cocaine-producing business together – a conviction for
conspiracy could lie. This was so since the goal of this (more general)
agreement would not be impossible in virtue of the particular white powder
having no capacity to yield cocaine.[419]
3.79
In The People (Attorney General) v Sullivan[420] there is obiter dictum
suggesting an impossible attempt is still an attempt. Sullivan
could be cited in support of a claim that impossible conspiracies are still
conspiracies in Irish law. For suppose that the defendant in Sullivan
had not been acting alone but had been in cahoots with someone in her efforts
to get extra pay through deception. It is difficult to imagine the
Supreme Court having being more indulgent to the defendant had she been acting
pursuant to an agreement than they were to her when she was acting alone.
In sum, in light of Supreme Court dictum in Sullivan, for the law
on inchoate offences to be consistent, the position in Ireland regarding
impossible conspiracies is that they are still conspiracies. This is at
odds with the interpretation of the common law applied in England, as outlined
above.[421]
It is noted that statute in England and Wales now criminalises impossible
conspiracies.
3.80
It is noted that debate about impossibility regarding inchoate offences
invariably focuses on attempt.[422] Considerations for conspiracy and
for incitement flow from the analysis of attempt.
3.81
There is much attraction in the common sense approach that a conspiracy
is a conspiracy and just because circumstances beyond the knowledge of the
conspirators mean that the specific criminal plan will not be realised does not
change this. So called impossible conspiracies should still be
criminal. Where what the would-be conspirators plan to do is not really
criminal (or unlawful) even though they think it is, the definition of
conspiracy is simply not made out and, therefore, the notion of impossibility
is not needed to prevent liability from attaching.
3.82
The Commission provisionally recommends that impossibility should not
bar liability for conspiracy.
3.83
Abandoning a conspiracy refers to where one or more of the parties to a
conspiracy withdraw or discontinue agreeing to, or being a party to, the
conspiracy. The question is whether this means they (the withdrawing
parties) have a defence to, or are otherwise not liable for, conspiracy.
As with impossible conspiracies the position in Ireland regarding abandoned
conspiracies is unclear. The parallel inference to that made above[423]
can be made: because the Supreme Court in Sullivan[424] stated, obiter, that an
abandoned attempt is still an attempt, so too abandoned conspiracies are still
conspiracies. This position would accord with the dominant common law
position.
3.84
The arguments for and against allowing a defence of abandonment for
attempt are relevant to conspiracy. But there is an important
consideration relevant to whether the law should allow a defence of abandonment
for conspiracy that is not present regarding abandoned attempts. For the
most part, with attempts a simple discontinuance of the attempt means the
substantive offence will not come about. If the actor abandons her
effort, yet the substantive offence nonetheless occurs, then a charge for the
substantive offence, rather than for attempting it, is appropriate. This
is obvious; it is mentioned here merely to emphasise that the law on abandoning
attempt does not really have to cover the situation where an abandoned attempt
nonetheless results in the target offence occurring. But with conspiracy,
and incitement for that matter, simple withdrawal might have no effect in
stopping the substantive offence (or unlawful acts) from happening, since the
other parties involved may continue on towards the target. The way to
account for this factor is to stipulate that in order to quality for an
abandonment defence the withdrawing party must not merely withdraw but must
take a positive step towards preventing the completion of the substantive
offence or unlawful acts. Indeed this consideration can be seen at work
in section 5.03(6) of the Model Penal Code, which provides:
“It is an affirmative defence that the actor, after
conspiring to commit a crime, thwarted the success of the conspiracy, under
circumstances manifesting a complete and voluntary renunciation of his criminal
purpose.”
3.85
Under the MPC it is not enough to make an effort to prevent the aim of
the conspiracy being realised; it is required to achieve the result of
preventing it, and furthermore, the conspiracy must have failed precisely because
of the withdrawing party’s work to foil it. In contrast, for attempt
under the MPC, it is a defence that the actor “abandoned his effort to commit
the crime or otherwise prevented its commission”. It is noted that it is
not essential to make the abandonment defence for conspiracy as exacting as it
is in the MPC. Nevertheless, the MPC model has the advantage (from the
point of view of being relatively acceptable to those who adhere to the common
law position) that, insofar as it allows for only a very restrictive defence,
its adoption does not represent a radical change from the common law position
where there is no such defence.
3.86
As with attempt,[425]
it may in principle be desirable to have a law on conspiracy that takes account
of abandonment. But for conspiracy, simple abandonment is not sufficient
to deserve exculpation. Also, the option open with attempt regarding
building in the absence of abandonment into its positive definition is not open
for conspiracy. Accordingly, an affirmative defence along the lines of
the MPC provision is the relevant option.
3.87
The Commission invites
submissions on whether there should be a defence available to a charge of
conspiracy for thwarting its success.
4
4.01
It is a criminal offence to incite a crime. In Ireland the common
law offence of incitement[426]
has been left unaltered by statute, though new incitement offences, such as
incitement to hatred, have been enacted.[427] Incitement to hatred, however, is
not an instance of common law incitement as there is no crime of hatred and
common law incitement attaches only to crimes.
4.02
The actus reus of incitement is the act of inciting, a
communication to someone else that seeks to persuade or pressure them to commit
a crime. The mens rea of incitement is intention that the
incitement be acted upon. For the purpose of discussing incitement this
Paper will refer to the person delivering the incitement as the incitor and the
intended recipient will be referred to as the incitee. It is key to note
that the incitee does not have to act upon the incitement. If the incitee
does indeed perform the incited crime, the incitor may be in turn be liable for
that crime via secondary liability. Nor does the incitee even have to be
influenced in any way towards committing the incited crime.[428]
4.03
A much quoted judicial passage from South Africa illustrates the breadth
of the actus reus of incitement:
“An inciter ... is one who reaches and seeks to influence the
mind of another to the commission of a crime. The machinations of
criminal ingenuity being legion, the approach to the other's mind may take many
forms, such as a suggestion, proposal, request, exhortation, gesture, argument,
persuasion, inducement, goading or the arousal of cupidity.”[429]
When incitement to murder is charged in Ireland it is
charged as soliciting murder contrary to section 4 of the Offences Against
the Person Act 1861. The formula prescribed for constituting the
offence is “solicit, encourage, persuade, or endeavour to persuade, or [ ]
propose to any person, to murder any other person …”[430]
4.04
The English Court of Appeal in R v Marlow[431] suggested “encourage” captures the actus
reus of incitement as well as any other word. But according to the
English courts,[432]
pressure and threats can also constitute incitement. “Encourage” might
tend to obscure this form of incitement. The same can be said about
“request” – as in the incitor requests the incitee do a criminal act.
“Persuade” somewhat conveys the act of incitement so long as it is remembered
that a guilty incitor need not have succeeded in persuading the incitee to act;
“persuasion” alone implies a degree of success which is not at all necessary
for guilt. In the United States, incitement is called solicitation.
This word emphasises a central example of incitement where someone requests the
performance of a criminal act for reward.
4.05
Under common law the communication must reach the person sought to be
incited. As O’Brien CLJ
stated, “[t]here must be evidence that the incitement reached the persons
intended to be affected wherever they are …”.[433] To repeat the definition given by
Holmes JA: “An inciter ... is one who reaches and seeks to influence the
mind of another to the commission of a crime.”[434] If the communication does not
reach the intended recipient – suppose a letter containing the encouragement to
commit crime is intercepted by the police – then attempt to incite can be
charged.[435]
The American Law Institute’s Model Penal Code (MPC) takes a different
approach to that of the common law. It effectively includes attempted
incitement under the scope of incitement by providing that it is not necessary
for the communication to reach the incitee. Section 5.02(2) of the MPC
provides it “is immaterial … that the actor fails to communicate with the
person he solicits to commit a crime if his conduct was designed to effect such
communication”.
4.06
The Court of Criminal Appeal[436] has recognised as settled that the
incitement does not have to succeed in order for the offence of incitement to
be made out. That is, the incitement does not have to be acted
upon. Furthermore, though the incitement must reach the mind of another
and seek to influence it, it does not have to actually influence their mind; it
is not necessary that the incitee have contemplated doing the incited offence
as a result of the incitement. Accordingly, it is possible to convict for
incitement where the person incited, the incitee, is an undercover police
officer.[437]
4.07
In The People (Attorney General) v Capaldi[438] the Court of Criminal Appeal
held, obiter, that a mere expression of desire that a certain (criminal)
outcome happen is not an incitement. In Capaldi the defendant
indicated to a doctor that he would like for a girl to have an abortion and
that there was ample money available for such a service. The Court held
that it was open to the jury to find that this communication by the defendant
was an effort at persuasion and hence an act of incitement. According to
the Court, the defendant’s mentioning of money was crucial in rendering his
action capable of being considered an incitement; if he had mentioned merely
that he wished for the girl to have an abortion, liability for incitement could
not attach.
4.08
Care needs to be exercised with this obiter dictum outside of the
particular facts of Capaldi. Certainly it cannot be concluded that
an expression of desire for an outcome can never be incitement. In
some contexts what is mere expression of desire may operate just as effectively
as an express request or encouragement to do a crime. The mens rea
of the speaker is key. That is, whether the expression of desire is made
with the intention that the listener will go on to bring about the outcome
desired. Consider a “crime boss” expressing their desire for some person
to be harmed, or one party to an extra-marital affair saying to her lover how
she wishes her husband would die. In these examples the mens rea
may well be such that the expression of desire is rendered criminal incitement.
4.09
In addition, it can be noted that Capaldi[439] proceeds on the basis that there is
authority for the proposition that mere expression of desire is not
incitement. The principal authority cited is the dicta of Le Blanc
J in R v Higgins stating:
“It is contended that the offence charged … is no
misdemeanour because it amounts only to a bare wish or desire of the mind to do
an illegal act. If that were so, I agree that it would not be
indictable. But this is a charge of an act done, namely, an actual
solicitation of a servant to rob his masters, and not merely a wish or desire
that he should do so.”[440]
It is crucial to note – as was not done in Capaldi –
that this dicta distinguishes from incitement mere wish or desire, not
the mere expression of wish or desire. The central question for
the Court of Criminal Appeal in Capaldi was really one of mens rea
– whether the defendant really intended to induce the doctor to perform an
abortion. The defendant’s appeal would have been difficult to make out
when centred on this issue. Hence, the defence appeal centred on a claim
that the jury was not properly instructed on the difference between mere
expression of desire and incitement. As a result of this defence
strategy, the judgment disposes of the case by reference to the difference
between an expression of desire and an incitement, and an opportunity for a
judicial statement of the mens rea of incitement was missed.
4.10
Incitement can occur despite the incitor not having met, nor even
communicated directly with, the incitee. For example, where a person pays
a subscription fee to a child pornography website, they may be liable for
inciting the distribution of child pornography despite the payment receiving
process being automated.[441]
The incitee in this case is the person operating the child pornography
business, who is capable of being encouraged to continue their criminal
enterprise by people paying subscription fees.
4.11
Incitement at common law does not require a specific individual be
incited. In R v Most[442] a newspaper article encouraging
political assassinations addressed to the world at large constituted incitement
to murder. Indeed incitement has been used in more recent prosecutions
against advocates of terrorism. Soliciting murder[443] was the most serious charge secured
against some Islamic extremists who encouraged Muslims to attack non-Muslims.[444]
4.12
The English courts have held that advertising a device that detects
police speed traps could be incitement even though there was no express
encouragement to use the device.[445] A similar result was reached by
the English Court of Appeal in Marlow[446] where the defendant had written a book
explaining how to cultivate cannabis plants. Liability for incitement
could attach despite the book not having expressly encouraged the criminal
activity it explained.
4.13
Someone who helps or facilitates another in the commission of a crime is
liable for that crime. The Criminal Law Act 1997 provides, “[a]ny
person who aids, abets, counsels or procures the commission of an indictable
offence shall be liable to be indicted, tried and punished as a principal
offender.”[447]
But where someone, for example, lends a van for the purpose of
trafficking drugs, liability will not attach to the lender if the special part
crime of trafficking drugs is not completed or attempted. Incitement does
not catch the person who assists unattempted crimes if the “assistance” did not
involve encouragement or another action that can constitute incitement.
Thus there is a perceived gap in criminal liability at common law which is
discussed in more detail below.[448]
4.14
The actus reus of incitement has not generated as much
controversy as the actus reus of attempt. Questions arising when
codifying incitement are discussed in this section. More wide-reaching
reform options for incitement are discussed below.
4.15
To what extent should a code provision on incitement seek to define the actus
reus of incitement? In the Draft Criminal Code of the Law Commission
for England and Wales the verb “incite” was preferred to “encourage” and no
further explanation or definition of “incite” was thought necessary.
Under this approach the common law cases and, in particular, the definition
provided by Holmes JA[449]
would continue to be relied on for more detailed meaning of the act of
incitement. A different approach was opted for in Victoria where, in a
definitions section, the criminal code provides that “incite includes to
command, request, propose, advise, encourage, or authorise”.[450] The American Law Institute’s
Model Penal Code (MPC) uses “commands, encourages or requests” to, in effect,
summarise the Holmes JA definition in less words again. This formula was
called vague by commentators who went on to endorse “commands, induces,
entreats, or otherwise endeavours to persuade”.[451] Nevertheless, recent codification
proposals in America have repeated the MPC formula.[452] For incitement to murder, Irish
law already relies on the formula “solicit, encourage, persuade, or endeavour
to persuade, or [ ] propose”.[453] The Canadian Criminal Code
employs “counsels” to describe incitement.[454]
4.16
It is noted that the verb(s) used in a code provision to describe the actus
reus of incitement also, in most codes, provide the sole guidance on the mens
rea of incitement. The code provisions seem to presuppose that the
verbs used to describe a physical action also entail the state of mind with
which that action is done. In other words, to use an example, to say
someone “commanded” someone else is to imply that what was done was
intentional. However, this idea of the action entailing the state of mind
that accompanies it can only go so far. It is easy to imagine someone
“encouraging” another unintentionally, for example, an Islamic cleric condemns
Western culture in harsh words might in fact “encourage” his audience towards
terrorist acts though this is not his purpose, his purpose being to point out immoral
behaviour as he sees it. The UK’s Terrorism Act 2006, section 1,
has enacted an offence of encouragement of terrorism, which can be made out on
the basis of what a public audience was likely to infer they were being
encouraged to do, rather than what the speaker believes he is
encouraging. Celebrating or praising terrorist acts (very widely defined)
is provided to be a ground for inferring encouragement of terrorism and the
2006 Act expressly provides that the offence can be committed recklessly.
This new offence, therefore, criminalises a much wider sphere of conduct than
common law incitement.
4.17
The MPC’s formula of “commands,
encourages or requests” provides a neat summary of what incitement encompasses
and has proved popular in recent codification movements in the United
States. It could be used as a statement of common law incitement in the
general part of a criminal code.
4.18
The Commission provisionally recommends that the formula “commands,
encourages or requests” be used to codify the actus reus of incitement.
4.19
Under the definition of incitement in the Draft Criminal Code of the Law
Commission for England and Wales a person is guilty of incitement if he
“incites another … and … intends or believes that the other, if he acts as
incited, shall or will do so with the fault required for the offence or
offences.”[455]
On a number of occasions the English courts have stated that this
definition is an accurate description of common law incitement.[456]
This is questionable, however, since the Law Commission for England and
Wales’s definition includes “intends or believes” while the common law
judgments tend to imply “intends” only. There is, however, a dearth of
judicial definition of the mens rea of incitement. In the seminal
case of R v Higgins[457]
the definition of incitement is not elaborated on beyond “solicit”. In R
v Most[458]
“intends” is explicitly mentioned when describing solicitation of murder.
As with “attempt”, “incite” connote intentional activity; to say that the
defendant incited or solicited a crime is to imply that they did so
intentionally.
4.20
Had the Law Commission for England and Wales’s definition used “intends
and believes” rather than “intends or believes” it would have been closer to
describing the existing common law position.[459] Indeed the Law Commission for
England and Wales in 2006[460]
approved a statement of the mens rea of incitement as intention plus
knowledge.[461]
In this context, intention applies to the consequences of the incitee
receiving the incitement or encouragement to crime. Knowledge includes
belief and refers to the need for the incitor to know that all the
circumstances and facts were in place such that, if the incitee carries out the
incitement, a crime will be committed.
4.21
Consistency between mens rea for attempt and incitement in both
requiring intention can be somewhat explained historically by reference to the
common ancestry of incitement and attempt. R v Higgins was a
classic case of incitement: the defendant solicited a servant to steal.
Yet the convoluted indictment boiled down to attempted larceny, and the appeal
court treated the case as one of attempt.[462] The same normative arguments for
keeping mens rea restricted to intention for attempts apply to
incitement.[463]
4.22
Direct intention, where the incitor’s aim is to cause a specific crime
is clearly sufficient. There are cases suggesting oblique intention,
where the incitor’s primary aim is something other – for example, making money
– than causing a specific crime also suffices.
[464]
4.23
It is noted that while the actus reus of incitement does not
require the incitee to actually be incited, the mens rea requires the
incitor intend the communication to actually incite its recipient. For
example, the law does not catch as incitement words that are meant to be a joke
or are otherwise not delivered seriously. Though new special part
offences in the UK such as encouragement of terrorism could conceivably be
committed by a speaker who intends merely to joke or engage in satire.
This is so because recklessness suffices as mens rea for this new
statutory offence.[465]
4.24
Given the maxim “ignorance of the law is no excuse” it can be suggested
that it is not necessary for the incitor to know or believe that the incited
act, if carried out, amounts to a criminal offence. If a customer in a
shop requested material that constitutes child pornography they may be guilty
of inciting distribution of child pornography.[466] Liability for this offence is
unaffected by the fact that the customer was unaware that child pornography was
criminalised or was unaware that the material he or she requested constituted
child pornography under the relevant legislation.[467]
4.25
But it is necessary for the accused to know or believe that the person
they are inciting will have the particular state of mind that happens to
satisfy the mens rea for the crime incited.[468]
4.26
The requirement that the defendant have knowledge of the circumstances
in which the incited act will be carried out can be satisfied other than by
showing actual knowledge. If a defendant wilfully shuts his eyes to the
reality of the circumstances he cannot claim to have no knowledge of them.
In this regard it might be said that recklessness as to circumstances suffices
as a component of the mental element of incitement, even though at the same
time intention as to consequences is required.[469]
4.27
There are a number of cases from England that purport to apply the
common law but serve to complicate the account of the mens rea of
incitement described thus far. There is suggestion, for instance, that
the incited act need not be intended if the incitor believes it is likely to be
carried out as a result of the incitement.[470] In Invicta Plastics Ltd v
Clare[471]
the defendants had advertised a device that could, among other things, be used
for detecting road speed traps, such use without a licence was criminal.
The Divisional Court was satisfied that a conviction for incitement could be
maintained despite it not being established that the defendants intended the
devices to be used. It was sufficient that they believed it likely the
devices would be used. Perhaps too much should not be read into this
decision since on the facts it could be inferred that the defendants intended
the devices to be used as that would mean satisfied customers leading on, it
might be supposed, to more profit. In other words, the defendants in Invicta
can be considered as having oblique intention that their devices be used in a
criminal manner.
4.28
A particularly problematic case is R v Shaw.[472] The defendant, an employee of a
car leasing company, had induced a colleague to accept false invoices as
authentic and issue cheques on them. The defendant was charged with
incitement to obtain money by deception. The defendant testified at trial
that his purpose was to expose flaws in his employer’s security
arrangements. The Court of Appeal held that if the jury believed the
defendant’s testimony they were entitled to acquit. The problem with this
decision is that for the purpose of incitement the relevant mens rea is
the intention that relates to what the incitee will do, not what is the
incitor’s overall purpose. The incitee in this case was unaware – and no
effort had been made by the defendant to make him aware – that the scam had an
ultimately laudable objective. Therefore, were the incitee to carry out
what he was encouraged to do (in fact, the incitee in Shaw had issued
one cheque on foot of a bogus invoice) he would be committing a crime and this
is precisely what the defendant intended, this being so even if the defendant’s
testimony is assumed to have been truthful. The definition of incitement
was made out in the facts of Shaw; commentators regard the decision as
anomalous.[473]
4.29
The Shaw decision is unsound. It departs from common law
incitement and there is no apparent reason why the law should go in that
direction. The analysis of criminal attempt in Chapter 2 above,[474]
which suggested attempt have its ordinary meaning and therefore be considered
intentional activity, applies to incitement. As with attempt the notion
of intention for incitement should encompass both direct and oblique intention.
4.30
The Commission provisionally recommends that the mens rea of
incitement should remain as intention that the incited act be carried out.
4.31
A specific crime must be incited for common law incitement.
Significantly, the person incited, the incitee, must be capable of being guilty
of the crime they have been incited to do. In R v Whitehouse[475]
the English Court of Appeal held that the defendant could not be convicted of
inciting his 15 year old daughter to commit incest (by having sex with him)
because, in the event she complied with the request, she would not be liable
for incest; such offences exist to protect rather than criminalise girls of her
age. Incitement was not made out in Whitehouse because in the
circumstances (the incitee being exempted from liability for incest) what was
incited was not really criminal. After Whitehouse in England a
specific crime was enacted of inciting a girl under 16 to commit incest, which
in turn was replaced with an offence that protected boys also. The
holding in Whitehouse still stands, however, as a general common law
rule for incitement.
4.32
Whitehouse can be viewed as a case where the definition of
incitement was not fully made out because what was encouraged was not criminal
in the circumstances. The case of R v Curr[476] can be understood on this basis
too. The decision has been criticised for distorting the mens rea
of incitement[477]
in that it confuses the mens rea of the incitee for the mens rea
of the incitor. The defendant in Curr operated a lending scheme
where he gave advance cash for family allowance vouchers, which he then had some
women cash in at a later date. At issue was whether the women he employed
to cash in the vouchers knew what they were doing was impermissible, it being
criminal to obtain payment for vouchers that did not belong to the claimant
(outside certain circumstances) knowing that it was impermissible to do
this. The Court of Appeal held that the defendant was entitled to an
acquittal of the incitement charge if indeed the women did not know what they
were doing was impermissible. This decision might be understood as
allowing acquittal on the basis of lack of mens rea on the part of the
defendant – that somehow if the incitee does not in fact have mens rea
then the incitor also does not have the requisite mens rea either.
If the decision rests on this basis it is clearly incorrect. Rather, to
make sense of the Curr decision, it must be seen as recognising that if
the incitee when carrying out the incited act lacks a crucial mens rea
element (in this case knowledge that claiming payments for someone else’s vouchers
was not permitted) then the definition of incitement is not made out just as it
is not made out in Whitehouse, that is, for want of something criminal
to have been incited. Considering common law incitement as consisting of
three ingredients – (1) an act, (2) mens rea, and (3) relation to a
special part crime – the conviction in Curr, it is here suggested, did
not stick for want of ingredient (3) rather than for want of ingredient (2).
4.33
The requirement that the incitee would be criminally liable if he or she
carry out the incited conduct has a number of implications. It means that
a child deemed incapable of crime cannot be incited. It has been
recognised that where an adult instructs a child to steal something, the adult
– prior to the child actually obtaining the item – may be guilty of an attempt
to steal since the adult has tried to commit theft through an innocent
agent. A logical implication that a court would likely not recognise
arises where the incitement takes the form of pressure and threats such that
the incitee would have a defence of duress in the event they carry out the
incited conduct. It is difficult to imagine a court allowing a defendant
to avoid incitement liability on the basis his or her incitement was of a
threatening nature.[478]
4.34
In R v Curr[479] it was held that a summary offence suffices at common law
for the crime incited.
4.35
It is possible to incite a crime to be committed against yourself,
provided that the absence of consent is not an element of the incited crime.[480]
So you can be guilty of incitement to murder where you encourage somebody
to kill you; but you are logically precluded from inciting someone to assault
you.
4.36
Legislation has made it criminal to incite some non-criminal
conduct. An example is the Prohibition of Incitement to Hatred Act
1989. Hatred alone, even when racist, is not a crime. But the
1989 Act makes it criminal to incite racial hatred (among other types of
hatred). Incitement to hatred is not an example of the common law
relational incitement because the conduct incited, in the absence of the
legislature enacting an offence of simply racial hatred, is not criminal.
Rather, incitement to hatred is a special part offence that so happens to use
the concept of incitement, albeit with some additional novelty.[481]
4.37
There is case law suggesting an inchoate offence can be the conduct
incited. Incitement to conspire was recognised at common law.[482]
Often, inciting an agreement to commit a crime would amount to an
incitement to commit that crime. In England and Wales, incitement to
conspire has been expressly abolished by statue;[483] but there has been no such development
in Ireland. Incitement to attempt has not been recognised in any case,
but it is believed to be a possible crime.[484] This is doubtful, however, since
the mens rea requirement for incitement of intention that the incited
act be carried out is not present if the incited act is merely intended to be
attempted. Incitement to incite has been recognised at common law.[485]
In contrast to attempting to attempt or conspiring to conspire,
incitement to incite is a plausible charge. Once again the concerns about
double inchoate liability expressed in Chapter 2 above[486] apply.
4.38
Regarding the question
of what can be criminally incited, the Commission sees to no reason to
provisionally recommend other than a rationalisation of the common law
position, that is, incitement attaches to crimes.
4.39
The Commission
provisionally recommends that all and only acts for which the incited person
can be criminally liable can be incited.
4.40
Incitements that result in completed or attempted crimes engage
secondary liability.[487]
But not all instances of (what would be) secondary liability (if the target
crime is completed or attempted) result in incitements. Incitement is not
committed by the person who assists (without encouraging) crimes that are never
even attempted. Furthermore, in this situation, secondary liability does
not apply because the target crime is neither completed nor attempted.
There seems to be inconsistency in that those who help – but do not actually
encourage – others to commit crime are not criminally liable if the target
crime is not in the end carried out. Yet it is thought that those who
assist unattempted crime are no less blameworthy than those who assist
completed crime.[488]
There is a gap in liability. It has been said that in England and Wales
conspiracy as a relational offence[489] and conspiracy
to defraud have been distorted and strained in an effort to compensate for this
gap.[490]
This is part of the argument proposing a new scheme of criminal liability
for assisting and encouraging crime.
4.41
The Law Commission for England and Wales have proposed two new offences,[491]
which have recently been enacted into law in England and Wales in the Serious
Crime Act 2007.
The actus reus is the same for both of these new offences: an act
capable of encouraging or assisting the commission of a criminal act. For
one of the two new offences (“the intent offence”), the mens rea is
intention that the criminal act be committed. For the other (“the belief
offence”), the mens rea is belief that the encouragement or assistance
will in fact encourage or assist plus a belief that the criminal act will be
committed.[492]
Liability for these offences is not dependent on the target offence being
committed or attempted. Thus, it is envisaged by the Law Commission for
England and Wales that these new offences will replace incitement as a
relational offence, and supplement rather than replace existing law on
secondary liability. The Law Commission for England and Wales
acknowledges the scope for overlap between the new offences and secondary
liability.
4.42
It might be thought that the intent offence is more serious of the
two. The punishment for both new offences is, however, the same – it
relates to that of the target offence and can be equal to it. But the
intent offence would be the more difficult to establish; it subsumes the belief
offence: as instances of the intent offence would also constitute the belief
offence, but not vice versa. Significantly, the new scheme rules out
attributing intention to assist or encourage crime on the sole basis that such
assistance or encouragement was a foreseeable consequence of what was done.[493]
Sullivan observes that this provision is crucial for differentiating the
intent and belief offences given the general practice of inferring intention of
foreseen consequences.[494]
4.43
It is important to note that the proposed offences engage principles and
theory lying behind general part secondary liability. They also serve to
greatly alter general part incitement. The Law Commission for England and
Wales worked on a report on secondary liability[495] at the same time as the report
proposing the new assisting and encouraging crime offences.[496] In order to evaluate fully the
new offences it would be necessary to survey and evaluate the existing
framework on secondary liability.
4.44
That said, some preliminary concerns about the
proposed offences can be noted. One concern is that the belief offence in
particular casts the net of liability very wide. “Encourage or assist” is
expansive; possibly more so than the sum of “encourage” and “assist” because it
is easier to put a borderline case into a general “assist or encourage”
category than it is to have to put it in either “assist” or “encourage”. Add to this the inchoate nature of the offences –
currently assisting someone in crime is only criminal if the crime is
completed. The idea that there is a gap in need of plugging can be
questioned. Not all behaviour that might be criminalised should be
criminalised. A hypothetical case mentioned[497] is where a taxi driver becomes
convinced he is driving his passengers to a destination where they will commit
a robbery. From the point of view of his own safety he prudently carries
them to their destination without protest. The taxi driver has assisted
crime and under the new scheme he may be guilty regardless of whether the crime
is carried out or whether it truly was planned to be carried out by the
passengers.
4.45
The Law Commission for England and Wales’s proposed scheme includes a
defence of reasonableness to the belief offence. Two reasons cast doubt
on how successful this defence would be in preventing conviction of those who
ought not to be convicted, or indeed the prosecution of those who ought not
even to be prosecuted in the first place. One reason is the vagueness and
uncertainty of the defence – reasonableness is undefined – different officials
at different stages of the criminal process may have a different idea of the
circumstances in which the defence operates. The second reason is that
the defendant bears the burden of proving the defence. As such it is a
departure from the presumption of innocence, which is founded among other
things on the very real concern about the difficulties that the ordinary
accused faces in proving things in court against the better equipped State.[498]
4.46
On balance the Commission is not convinced of the need to replace
incitement with a new offence of assisting or encouraging crime. The
Commission is particularly concerned that the new offence would cast the net of
criminal liability too wide.
4.47
The Commission provisionally recommends that the common law offence
of incitement should not be replaced with a new relational inchoate offence of
assisting or encouraging crime.
4.48
The act of incitement is essentially a speech act; criminalising
incitement restricts speech. As such, incitement interferes with freedom
of expression rights contained in the Constitution[499] and the European Convention on Human
Rights.[500]
Incitement offences have not had their constitutionality challenged in the
Irish courts. However, there have been challenges elsewhere.
4.49
In R v Marlow[501]
the author of a book describing how to grow and harvest cannabis was convicted
for inciting drug offences. The conviction in Marlow was for a
statutory incitement offence under section 19 of the Misuse of Drugs Act
1971.
This offence applies as common law incitement applies, that is, as a relational
inchoate offence; hence, the Marlow decision can be taken as an
interpretation of the common law. The defendant author in Marlow
sought a declaration from the European Court of Human Rights that his
conviction was in violation of Article 10 of the European Convention on Human
Rights protecting freedom of expression. The application was declared
inadmissible.[502]
The European Court of Human Rights acknowledged that the applicant’s
right to freedom of expression had been interfered with and that
decriminalisation of cannabis had been pursued in a number of Convention
States. But the Court held that the interference was justified and it was
within the State’s margin of appreciation to criminalise incitement to produce
cannabis.
4.50
On a number of occasions in the 20th Century the United
States Supreme Court has been asked to strike down sedition and incitement
offences as unconstitutional under the 1st Amendment of the US
Constitution. The leading decision is Brandenburg v Ohio[503]
in which the Supreme Court set out requirements that must be present in order
for an incitement offence to survive constitutional scrutiny. The Court
stated that mere advocacy of illegal action could not be punished, only
“advocacy [that] is directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action
and is likely to incite or produce such action.”
4.51
It has been observed that this holding is at odds with existing criminal
incitement in the United States and elsewhere.[504] In particular, the Brandenburg
test requires a likelihood that the speech will produce the illegal action it
encourages. As has been repeatedly emphasised above,[505] common law incitement and its statutory
equivalents can be committed once the communication reaches the incitee even
where there was little or no chance that the incited act would be carried
out. For example, in R v Goldman[506] an undercover police officer was
requested to supply child pornography, something which there was no likelihood
of happening. The Court nonetheless affirmed the conviction.
4.52
The Irish courts have not had occasion to comment on the relevance of
impossibility to incitement liability. The question is whether incitement
is precluded where the circumstances are such that it is impossible for the
offence incited to occur if the incitement is carried out? The question
could also be phrased in terms of a defence by asking whether it is a defence
to a charge of incitement to show that, even if the alleged incitement was
carried out, no offence could have been committed given the
circumstances. To illustrate with an example, is it incitement to murder
to instruct the murder of a particular person who, unbeknownst to you, is
already dead?
4.53
The English courts have had occasion to discuss impossible
incitements. Unlike impossibility in relation to attempt and conspiracy,
English statute has not touched on impossible incitement with the result that
the English courts have been endeavouring to apply the common law. The
common law position, as interpreted by the English Courts, is that incitement
cannot be committed where the particular target offence cannot be committed.
4.54
One type of case that might be thought of as involving an impossible
incitement is where no crime will be committed by the incitee if the incitement
is acted on. In R v Whitehouse[507] the Court of Appeal held that a father
could not be guilty of inciting incest when he encouraged his 15 year old
daughter to have sex with him since, if the daughter acted on the
encouragement, she would not be criminally liable since the offence of incest
exists to protect, not criminalise a person in her position. The Court of
Appeal held that in the circumstances the accused could be charged with
inciting his daughter to aid and abet him in committing incest. In the
aftermath of Whitehouse the UK Parliament enacted a specific offence of
inciting a girl under 16 to have incestuous sexual intercourse.[508]
Whitehouse is still authority for the proposition that liability for
incitement does not lie where the incitee would not be guilty of a crime if he
or she carries out the conduct incited. This position was reaffirmed by
the Court of Appeal in R v Clayton.[509]
4.55
In Whitehouse the definition of incitement is simply not made out
in the first place because the essential component that a crime be incited is
not present. Hence, Whitehouse is typically discussed in the
context of the elements of incitement rather than in the context of
impossibility. In R v Fitzmaurice[510] the defendant, on the advice of his
father, asked some men to take part in a robbery. Unknown to the
defendant he was being set up by his father; the planned robbery was a
sham. The Court of Appeal held that the case turned on the specificity of
the robbery incited. If what was incited was a robbery with specific
details and that robbery was impossible in the circumstances a conviction for
incitement could not stand. The Court in Fitzmaurice concluded that
the robbery incited was of a general nature and thus not impossible in the
circumstances.
4.56
Earlier, the English Court of Appeal in R v McDonough[511] held that
incitement could be made out where the defendant had encouraged a person to
handle stolen lamb carcasses that the defendant believed were in a particular
freezer when in fact no such carcasses existed.
4.57
As with attempt and conspiracy the common sense approach that relies on
the ordinary meaning of incitement suggests that impossibility should not
preclude liability.[512]
4.58
The Commission provisionally recommends that the impossibility should
not preclude liability for incitement.
4.59
Abandonment in the context of inchoate offences refers to the situation
where someone proceeding towards crime discontinues his or her efforts, no
longer intending that the crime be completed.[513] The question is whether liability
for an inchoate offence should still attach in light of the would-be perpetrator’s
abandonment of criminal intention. “Abandonment” is perhaps inapposite
when focusing on incitement given that, unlike attempt and conspiracy, once its
threshold has been passed the incitor need play no further part in bringing
about the target crime. As such an incitor cannot logically “abandon” an
incitement once it has been delivered. What he or she can do is make an
effort to undo any effect the incitement may have had. For example, a
person who originally solicited a contract killing might later request the
killing not be carried through.
4.60
There has been no Irish judicial discussion of this issue. The
American Law Institute’s Model Penal Code provides for a defence of
renunciation of criminal purpose:
“It is an affirmative defence that the actor, after
soliciting another person to commit a crime, persuaded him not to do so or
otherwise prevented the commission of the crime, under circumstances
manifesting a complete and voluntary renunciation of his criminal purpose.”[514]
This defence is onerous. It is not enough for the
incitor just to try, no matter how earnestly, to undo what he or she might have[515]
set in motion. He or she has got to succeed. Nor is it enough that
the incited crime did not come to pass in circumstances where the incitor was
seeking to undo the incitement. Rather, the non-occurrence of the incited
crime has to be because of the incitor’s actions in undoing the
incitement.
4.61
The Commission invites submissions on whether it should be a defence
to an incitement charge to have prevented the incited act from occurring.
5
5.01
The Commission’s provisional recommendations:
5.02
The Commission provisionally recommends codification of the proximate
act approach to defining the actus reus of attempt and invites submissions on which formula of
words should be used. [Paragraph 2.65]
5.03
The Commission invites submissions on whether a list of illustrative
examples should accompany a definition of attempt. [Paragraph 2.66]
5.04
The Commission invites submissions on whether there should be explicit
recognition that where a substantive offence can be committed by omission,
attempting that offence can also be committed by omission. [Paragraph
2.69]
5.05
The Commission provisionally recommends that the issue of what can
constitute a criminal attempt should be a question of law. [Paragraph
2.75]
5.06
The Commission invites submissions on whether a general offence of
criminal preparation is desirable. [Paragraph 2.85]
5.07
The Commission provisionally recommends that the mens rea of
attempt should continue to be intention, where intention means both direct and
oblique intention. [Paragraph 2.99]
5.08
The Commission invites submissions on whether the definition of mens
rea for criminal attempt should employ an express
consequences/circumstances distinction. [Paragraph 2.107]
5.09
The Commission provisionally recommends that intra-jurisdictional
attempts be expressly recognised as attempts triable within the
jurisdiction. [Paragraph 2.124]
5.10
The Commission invites submissions on whether both indictable and
summary offences should be capable of being criminally attempted.
[Paragraph 2.128]
5.11
The Commission provisionally recommends that impossibility should not
bar attempt liability. [Paragraph 2.152]
5.12
The Commission invites submissions on whether abandonment should have
relevance to attempt liability. [Paragraph 2.163]
5.13
The Commission provisionally recommends that conspiracy continue to be
based on the concept of agreement, which should have its ordinary
meaning. [Paragraph 3.08]
5.14
The Commission provisionally recommends that jurisdiction be claimed for
cross border conspiracies generally. [Paragraph 3.24]
5.15
The Commission provisionally recommends the abolition of the rule that
spouses cannot conspire together. [Paragraph 3.28]
5.16
The Commission
provisionally recommends that conspiracy not be made out where only one party
to it has criminal capacity. [Paragraph 3.34]
5.17
The Commission provisionally recommends that exemption from liability
for the target offence of a conspiracy on the part of one or more parties
should not cause other parties to the conspiracy to escape conspiracy
liability. [Paragraph 3.35]
5.18
The Commission provisionally recommends that the mens rea of
conspiracy include a requirement for intention that the conspiratorial plan
actually be carried out. [Paragraph 3.42]
5.19
The Commission provisionally recommends that conspiracy be limited to
agreements to do criminal acts and that the common law offences of conspiracy
to corrupt public morals, to outrage public decency, and to effect a public
mischief be abolished. [Paragraph 3.75]
5.20
The Commission invites submissions on whether conspiracy to defraud
should be retained. [Paragraph 3.76]
5.21
The Commission provisionally recommends that impossibility should not
bar liability for conspiracy. [Paragraph 3.82]
5.22
The Commission invites submissions on whether there should be a defence
available to a charge of conspiracy for thwarting its success. [Paragraph
3.87]
5.23
The Commission provisionally recommends that the formula “commands,
encourages or requests” be used to codify the actus reus of
incitement. [Paragraph 4.18]
5.24
The Commission provisionally recommends that the mens rea of
incitement should remain as intention that the incited act be carried
out. [Paragraph 4.30]
5.25
The Commission provisionally recommends that all and only acts for which
the incited person can be criminally liable can be incited. [Paragraph
4.39]
5.26
The Commission provisionally recommends that the common law offence of
incitement should not be replaced with a new relational inchoate offence of
assisting or encouraging crime. [Paragraph 4.47]
5.27
The Commission provisionally recommends that the impossibility should
not preclude liability for incitement. [Paragraph 4.58]
5.28
The Commission invites submissions on whether it should be a defence to
an incitement charge to have prevented the incited act from occurring.
[Paragraph 4.61]
[1]
See Report on the
Third Programme of Law Reform 2008-2014 (LRC 86 – 2007). Project 19
in the Third Programme commits the Commission to examine inchoate offences, on
which the Commission began work under its Second Programme of Law Reform
2000-2007.
[2]
See Report on Homicide:
Murder and Involuntary Manslaughter (LRC 87 – 2008), which completed the
Commission’s work under Project 17 in the Third Programme of Law Reform (on
which the Commission had published two Consultation Papers under its Second
Programme).
[3]
Project 18 in the Third
Programme commits the Commission to examine the defences of provocation,
legitimate defence (including self-defence) and duress and necessity. Under its
Second Programme of Law Reform 2000-2007, the Commission published three
Consultation Papers on these defences and is currently preparing a Report on
them.
[4]
Established under Part
14 of the Criminal Justice Act 2006.
[5]
Available at
www.criminalcode.ie
[6]
As recommended in the
Report of the Expert Group on the Codification of the Criminal Law Codifying
the Criminal Law (Government Publications 2004), available at
www.justice.ie
[7]
See Codifying the
Criminal Law at paragraphs 2.89 and 2.99.
[8]
Criminal Law
Codification Advisory Committee First Programme of Work 2008-2009 at
paragraph 1.04, available at www.criminalcode.ie
[9]
This Commission’s
previous work on specific areas of criminal law, such as non-fatal offences
against the person, formed the basis for some of the mini-codes already enacted
which will be incorporated into the inaugural Draft Criminal Code Bill:
see Codifying the Criminal Law at paragraph 1.69.
[10]
Another example is endangerment
in section 13 of the Non-Fatal Offences Against the Person Act 1997.
[11]
Section 9 of the Firearms
and Offensive Weapons Act 1990.
[12]
Report of the Expert Group on
the Codification of the Criminal Law Codifying the Criminal Law
(Government Publications 2004) at paragraph 2.86.
[13]
Codifying the Criminal Law
at paragraph 2.89.
[14]
This sequence is used in a
number of textbooks including Charleton, McDermott, and Bolger Criminal Law
(Butterworths 1999), McAuley and McCutcheon, Criminal Liability (Round
Hall Press 2000) and Hanly An Introduction to Irish Criminal Law (2nd
ed Gill & Macmillan 2006).
[15]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at Chapter 9.
[16] For
an account of the evolution of inchoate liability in the wide sense see McAuley
and McCutcheon Criminal Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at Chapter 9,
especially at 401-412. See also Law Reform Commission of Canada Secondary
Liability: Participation in Crime and Inchoate Offences (Working Paper 45
1985) at 9-14.
[17]
R v Schofield
(1784) Cald 397. See McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal Liability
(Round Hall Press 2000) at 409-410.
[18]
(1801) 2 East 5.
[19]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 422-423.
[20]
See Chapter 3 below at
paragraphs 3.55 and 3.68. See also McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 422-430.
[21]
Sayre “Criminal
Conspiracy” (1922) 35 HLR 393, at 397.
[22]
See McAuley and
McCutcheon Criminal Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 423.
[23]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 424, citing 1 Hawk PC c72 paragraph 1
and 4 Bl. Com. 136.
[24]
Sayre “Criminal Conspiracy”
(1922) 35 HLR 393, at 402.
[25]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 424.
[26]
(1721) 8 Mod 10.
[27]
(1832) 110 ER 485, 487, per
Denman CJ.
[28] “Man Gets
Life Sentence for Attempted Murder” The Irish Times 5 May 2007.
[29]
Enker “Mens Rea and
Criminal Attempt” (1977) Am B Found Res J 845, at 850.
[30]
Dennis “The Rationale of
Criminal Conspiracy” (1977) 93 LQR 39. See also Law Commission for
England and Wales Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No
183 2007) at 25-35.
[31]
The Law Commission for England
and Wales notes that this observation does not have as much force today as it
formerly did in light of the many preparatory offences since enacted in England
and Wales. Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No
183 2007) at paragraph 2.11, footnote 9.
[32]
Dennis “The Rationale of
Criminal Conspiracy” (1977) 93 LQR 39, at 41.
[33]
See Law Commission for England
and Wales Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007)
at paragraphs 2.11-2.19.
[34]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 42, Ashworth Principles of Criminal
Law (5th ed Oxford University Press 2006) at 68, Dripps “The
Constitutional Status of the Reasonable Doubt Rule” (1987) 75 Calif L Rev 1665.
[35]
This draws on Lon Fuller’s
account of the rule of law and its value in Fuller The Morality of Law
(Yale University Press 1965). The Constitution of Ireland expressly
enshrines a number of these principles, for example, the prohibition of
retroactive criminalisation in Article 15.5.1º.
[36]
See Simmonds Central Issues
in Jurisprudence (2nd ed Sweet & Maxwell 2002) at chapter 7.
[37]
Law Reform Commission Consultation
Paper on Legitimate Defence (LRC CP 41-2006).
[38]
Legality is invoked 12 times
in the Report of the Expert Group on the Codification of the Criminal Law Codifying
the Criminal Law (Government Publications 2004).
[39]
See Chapter 3 below at paragraphs
3.64-3.76.
[40]
Leading writers include HLA
Hart, Glanville Williams, and Andrew Ashworth.
[41]
Proponents include Oliver W
Holmes, Antony Duff.
[42]
See below at paragraph 2.34.
[43]
See Enker “Mens Rea and
Criminal Attempt” (1977) Am B Found Res J 845, at 847.
[44]
Ormerod Smith & Hogan:
Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 400.
[45]
Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 5 citing R v Whybrow [1951] 35 Cr App
R 141, 147.
[46]
This draws on Law Reform
Commission of Canada Secondary Liability: Participation in Crime and
Inchoate Offences (Working Paper 45 1985) at 1-3.
[47]
Section 7(1) of the Criminal
Law Act 1997.
[48]
See Law Reform Commission Report
on Corporate Killing (LRC 77-2005) at 67-69.
[49]
See, for example, “Man gets
life sentence for attempted murder” The Irish Times 5 May 2007;
“Suspended term for wife who tried to kill family” The Irish Times 24
July 2007.
[50]
Section 2 of the Firearms
Act 1925 as amended.
[51]
Section 9 of the Firearms
and Offensive Weapons Act 1990.
[52]
Section 53 of the Road
Traffic Act 1961 as amended.
[53]
Section 21 of the Offences
Against the State Act 1939 as amended.
[54]
Section 3 of the Explosive
Substances Act 1883, substituted by section 4 of the Criminal Law
(Jurisdiction) Act 1976 and amended.
[55]
Section 4 of the Explosive
Substances Act 1883 as amended by section 15 of the Offences Against the
State (Amendment) Act 1998.
[56]
Section 21 of the Firearms
Act 1925 as amended.
[57]
See, for example, Hocking
“Conspiracy as a very enduring practice: Part I” [1998] 8 ICLJ 1 and
“Conspiracy as a very enduring practice: Part II” [1998] 8 ICLJ 121, Sayre
“Criminal Conspiracy” (1922) 35 Harv L Rev 393, Hadden “Conspiracy to Defraud”
(1966) Camb LJ 248.
[58]
Harrison v United States
7 F.2d 259, 263 (2d Cir. 1925).
[59]
Director of Public
Prosecutions “Statement of General Guidelines for Prosecutors” at 18, available
at http://www.dpp.ie/filestore/documents/E_Guidelines.pdf
[60]
A problem referred to as
“ossification of the criminal law”. See Report of the Expert Group on the
Codification of the Criminal Law Codifying the Criminal Law (Government
Publications 2004) at paragraph 1.108.
[61]
At paragraph 1.12.
[62]
Fuller The Morality of Law
(Yale University Press 1965), Raz “The Rule of Law and its Virtue” in Raz The
Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality (Oxford University Press
1979), Finnis Natural Law and Natural Rights (Clarendon Press 1980).
[63]
At paragraphs 4-6 of the
Introduction above.
[64]
See Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 394 discussing DPP v Knuller [1973]
AC 435.
[65]
Report of the Expert Group on
the Codification of the Criminal Law Codifying the Criminal Law
(Government Publications 2004) at paragraph 2.95.
[66]
Law Reform Commission Consultation
Paper on Legitimate Defence (LRC CP 41-2006).
[67]
[1952] IR 91, 93.
[68]
See comments of Walsh J
in People (Attorney General) v Sullivan [1964] IR 169, 200.
[69]
Attorney General v
Richmond (1935) 1 Frewen 28, R v Eagleton [1845-60] All ER 363; 169
ER 766; 6 Cox CC 559.
[70]
R v Eagleton
[1845-60] All ER 363, The People (Attorney General) v Thornton [1952] IR
91, 93, The People (Attorney General) v Sullivan [1964] IR 169, 195.
[71]
Gavan Duffy P in The
People (Attorney General) v England (1947) 1 Frewen 81, 83, Haughton v
Smith [1975] AC 476, 499, Law Commission for
England and Wales Consultation Paper Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183
2007) at paragraph 16.1.
[72]
Law Commission for
England and Wales Report on Attempt, and Impossibility in Relation to
Attempt, Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102 1980) at paragraph 2.45.
[73]
[1964] IR 169.
[74]
Thus, the Supreme Court
affirmed the conclusion of Teevan J in the High Court.
[75]
Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 274.
[76]
R v Eagleton [1855] 6
Cox CC 559, 571; 169 ER 826, 835, quoted by Walsh J at [1964] IR 169, 195-196.
[77]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 415. See Lord Diplock in Stonehouse
[1978] AC 55, 68. Note the suggestion of the Law Commission for England and
Wales that Lord Diplock should not be read as applying a last act test – Law
Commission for England and Wales Consultation Paper Conspiracy and Attempts
(CP No 183 2007) at paragraph 13.7.
[78]
[1855] 6 Cox CC 559, 571; 169
ER 826, 835-836.
[79]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Consultation Paper Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at
paragraph 13.3.
[80]
See discussion of meaning of
“proximate” in Law Commission for England and Wales Report on Attempt, and
Impossibility in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102
1980) at paragraph 2.48.
[81]
(1947) 1 Frewen 81.
[82]
(1947) 1 Frewen 81, 84.
[83]
The England judgment
cited R v Higgins (1801) 2 East 5, where words alone constituted an
attempt. In The People (Attorney General) v Thornton [1952] IR 91
an alleged attempt committed by words alone was held not to constitute an
attempt, but not for the reason that evidence disclosed mere words.
[84]
[1952] IR 91.
[85]
[1952] IR 91, 96-97.
[86]
[1952] IR 91.
[87]
[1952] IR 91, 93.
[88]
Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 274.
[89]
[1900] 2 QB 597.
[90]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Attempt, and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt,
Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102 1980) at paragraph 2.48, citing Concise
Oxford Dictionary (6th ed 1976).
[91]
Parke B’s judgment in Eagleton
[1855] 6 Cox CC 559, 571; 169 ER 826, 835-836 attains its greatest level of
coherence when his use of “proximate” is understood as this literal traditional
dictionary meaning.
[92]
The People (Attorney
General) v Sullivan [1964] IR 169.
[93]
As done by Duff Criminal
Attempts (Oxford University Press 1996) at 42, 44 and 48.
[94]
[1964] IR 169.
[95] In the
absence of evidence on point the Court assumed, in the defendant’s favour, that
she was below the 25 report mark when she made the false reports detailed in
evidence.
[96]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 417.
[97]
[1978] AC 55.
[98]
Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 41.
[99]
“Man Gets Life Sentence for
Attempted Murder” The Irish Times 5 May 2007.
[100]
Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 41.
[101]
See Gordon Criminal Law
(3rd ed Green & Sons 2000) at 209.
[102]
[1784] Cald 397.
[103]
[1784] Cald 397, 403.
[104]
Section 4(1) of the Criminal
Code Act 1899.
[105]
Buffalo Criminal Law Centre’s
translation. Available at http://wings.buffalo.edu/law/bclc/StGBframe.htm
[106]
Sturge Stephen: A Digest of
the Criminal Law (9th ed Sweet & Maxwell 1950).
[107]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Attempt, and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt,
Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102 1980) at paragraph 2.22.
[108]
Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 43.
[109]
Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 36.
[110]
Williams Criminal Law: The
General Part (Stevens & Sons 1953) at 632.
[111]
See Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 37 on the good of allowing locus
poenitentiae (a place for repentance), and thereby treating citizens as
autonomous agents.
[112]
Ashworth “Criminal Attempts
and the Role of Resulting Harm under the Code, and in the Common Law” (1988) 19
Rutgers LJ 725, at 750.
[113]
Salmond Jurisprudence, or
the Theory of the Law (3d ed Stevens & Haynes 1910). The section
on attempts was deleted from later editions of this work.
[114]
[1924] NZLR 865.
[115]
Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 50.
[116]
Section 72(3) of the Crimes
Act 1961 (NZ). Emphasis added.
[117]
[1967] 2 All ER 423.
[118]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 418-419, Gordon Criminal Law (3rd
ed Green & Sons 2000) at 195.
[119]
Translation of Article 56 of
Italian Penal Code from Rocco, Maitlin and Wise, The Italian Penal Code
(Sweet and Maxwell 1978) at 18.
[120]
525 F.2d 881 (5th
Cir.1976).
[121]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 421.
[122]
Duff discusses this example:
Duff Criminal Attempts (Oxford University Press 1996) at 51. See
also Dressler Cases and Materials on Criminal Law (3rd Ed Thomson West
2003) at 762.
[123]
See McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 420.
[124]
(1968) 52 Cr App R 614.
[125]
(1968) 52 Cr App R 614, 616,
per Parker LCJ.
[126]
(1968) 52 Cr App R 614, 617.
[127]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 420.
[128]
Davey v Lee [1967] 2
All ER 423, 427, adopting a formulation from Archbold Pleading, Evidence and
Practice (36th ed).
[129]
[1967] 2 All ER 423.
[130]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Attempt, and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt,
Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102 1980) at 86.
[131]
Williams “Wrong Turnings in
the Law of Attempt” [1991] Crim LR 416 at 417-418.
[132]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Attempt, and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt,
Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102 1980) at paragraph 2.47: “We have
reached the conclusion that, in regard to these cases, it is undesirable to
recommend anything more complex than a rationalisation of the present law.”
[133]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Attempt, and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt,
Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102 1980) at paragraph 2.48.
[134]
Williams “Wrong Turnings in
the Law of Attempt” [1991] Crim LR 416 at 417.
[135]
See Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 379 for example.
[136]
Ormerod Smith & Hogan:
Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 409.
[137]
Walsh J in The People
(Attorney General) v Sullivan [1964] IR 169, 195; Kennedy CJ in Attorney
General v Richmond (1935) 1 Frewen 28, 31; Haugh J in The People
(Attorney General) v Thornton [1952] IR 91, 93.
[138]
Ormerod Smith & Hogan:
Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 410. State v Otto
102 Idaho 250, 629 P.2d 646 (1981).
[139]
Especially in light of Law
Commission for England and Wales’s express efforts to formulate a law that
would not result in last act framework – the very reason why the language of
proximity was rejected. Law Commission for England and Wales Report on
Attempt, and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and Incitement
(No 102 1980) at paragraph 2.48.
[140]
The 1981 Act was read as
stating a last act test in Widdowson (1985) 82 Cr App R 314,
318-319. R v Geddes [1996] Crim LR 894 is seen by the Law
Commission for England and Wales as applying a test for attempt that is too
restricted. See Law Commission for England and Wales Consultation
Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at 14.15-14.16.
[141]
Osborn (1919) 84 JP 63.
[142]
[1997] Crim LR 746.
[143]
Ormerod Smith & Hogan:
Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 410 (footnote 370).
[144]
Ormerod Smith & Hogan:
Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 411.
[145]
Dennis “The Law Commission
Report on Attempt and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and
Incitement: (1) The Elements of Attempt” [1980] Crim LR 758, 768 commenting on
Law Commission for England and Wales Report on Attempt, and Impossibility in
Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102 1980). Dennis
re-affirms the critique in “The Criminal Attempts Act 1981” [1982] Crim LR 5 at
8.
[146]
See Dennis “The Law Commission
Report on Attempt and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and
Incitement: (1) The Elements of Attempt” [1980] Crim LR 758 at 768.
[147]
[1991] Crim LR 268.
[148]
JC Smith’s commentary [1991]
Crim LR 268 at 269.
[149]
[1996] Crim LR 894.
[150]
[1997] Crim LR 746.
[151]
Bingham CJ, Ognall and Astill
JJ.
[152]
Beldam LJ, Bracewell and Mance
JJ.
[153]
Most recently in Ormerod Smith
& Hogan: Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 410.
[154]
[1991] Crim LR 286.
[155]
[1996] Crim LR 894.
[156]
246 NY 334, 158 N.E. 888
(1927).
[157]
Wechsler, Jones and Korn “The
Treatment of Inchoate Crimes in the Model Penal Code of the American Law
Institute: Attempt, Solicitation, and Conspiracy” (1961) 61 Columbia Law Review
571 at 595.
[158]
Dennis “The Law Commission
Report on Attempt and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and
Incitement: (1) The Elements of Attempt” [1980] Crim LR 758 at 771-772.
[159]
The preparation offence is
envisaged as supplementing criminal attempt. See discussion in Law
Commission for England and Wales Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and
Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at paragraphs 16.26-16.57.
[160]
Final Report of the
Illinois Criminal Code Rewrite and Reform Commission (2003) and Final
Report of the Kentucky Penal Code Revision Project (2003). Professor
Paul H Robinson was the reporter in these instances.
[161]
Kentucky, Illinois and Georgia
are examples.
[162]
In R v Maunder (1966) 1
CCC 328, 377 it was stated that section 24 of the Criminal Code of Canada “is,
in effect, a codification of the common law.”
[163]
People (Attorney General) v Sullivan [1964] IR 169.
[164]
[1952] IR 91.
[165]
Quoted in Davey v Lee
[1967] 2 All ER 423, 425. See McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 418-422.
[166] See McAuley and
McCutcheon Criminal Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 445, footnote
267.
[167]
See Dennis “The Law Commission
Report on Attempt and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and
Incitement: (1) The Elements of Attempt” [1980] Crim LR 758 at 770-771 and
using Gibbins and Proctor (1918) 13 Cr App R 134. See also R v
Instan [1893] 1 QB 450, cited by Dennis “The Criminal Attempts Act 1981”
[1982] Crim LR 5 at 8, footnote 15.
[168]
See Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Attempt, and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt,
Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102 1980) at paragraph 2.105 saying attempt
concept not meaningful in relation to omissions.
[169]
Section 1 of Criminal Attempts
Act 1981 (England and Wales); Australian state codes including section 44
of the Australian Capital Territory Criminal Code 2002 and section 4 of
the Northern Territory Criminal Code.
[170]
Section 24 of the Criminal Code
of Canada; section 5.01 of the Model Penal Code; section 72 of the New
Zealand Crimes Act 1961; section 27 of the Samoa Crimes Ordinance
1961 section 27.
[171]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007).
[172]
Clause 49(3) of A Criminal Code
for England and Wales in Law Commission for England and Wales Report and
Draft Criminal Code Bill (No 177 1989).
[173]
Criminal Attempts Act 1981 (England
and Wales). Section 24(2) of the Canadian Criminal Code.
[174]
(1947) 1 Frewen 81, 84.
[175]
DPP v Stonehouse [1978] AC
55.
[176]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Report on Attempt, and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and
Incitement (No 102 1980) at paragraphs 2.50-2.52.
[177]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at
paragraphs 14.23-14.25. The Law Commission for England and Wales thus
recommends changing the existing rule, which put in place what was recommended
in Law Commission for England and Wales Report on Attempt, and Impossibility
in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102 1980) at
paragraphs 2.50-2.52.
[178]
See Dennis “The Law Commission
Report on Attempt and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and
Incitement: (1) The Elements of Attempt” [1980] Crim LR 758 at 768.
[179]
State v Reeves (1996) 916
S.W.2d 909, extracted in Dressler Cases and Materials on Criminal Law
(3rd ed Thomson West) at 763.
[180]
An example is section 44(8) of Australian
Capital Territory Criminal Code 2002.
[181]
See discussion of common law
doctrine of merger in Charleton, McDermott and Bolger Criminal Law
(Butterworths 1999) at 278.
[182]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007).
[183]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at
paragraph 12.6-12.7.
[184]
(1996) 160 JP 697; [1996] Crim LR
894.
[185]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at
paragraph 16.42.
[186]
D refers to the defendant. Law
Commission for England and Wales Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and
Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at paragraph 16.47 (footnotes omitted).
[187]
See Charleton, McDermott and Bolger Criminal
Law (Butterworths 1999) at 259, Marlin, “Attempts and the Criminal Law:
Three Problems” (1976) 8 Ottawa L Rev 518, 527.
[188]
Example taken from Horder “Varieties
of Intention, Criminal Attempts and Endangerment” (1994) 14 Legal Studies 335.
[189]
[1952] IR 91, 93.
[190]
Duff Intention, Agency and
Criminal Liability (Blackwell 1990) at 61.
[191]
Section 13(1) of the Non-Fatal
Offences Against the Person Act 1997.
[192]
The Commission has recently made
final its recommendation that mens rea for murder be expanded to
included a certain type of reckless killing. See Law Reform Commission Report
on Homicide: Murder and Involuntary Manslaughter (LRC 87-2008) and Consultation
Paper on Homicide: The Mental Element in Murder (LRC CP-2001).
[193]
R v Schofield [1784] Cald
397, 403; R v Whybrow [1951] 35 Cr App R 141.
[194]
[1985] ILRM 25, approving R v
Whybrow (1951) 35 Cr App R 141 and R v Mohan [1976] QB 1.
[195]
(1951) 35 Cr App R 141.
[196]
[1976] QB 1.
[198]
Lajoie v R [1974] SCR 399.
For criticism of Lajoie see Marlin “Attempts and the Criminal Law:
Three Problems” (1976) Ottawa L Rev 518 and MacKinnon “Making Sense of
Attempts” (1982) 7 Queen’s LJ 253.
[199]
Ancio (1984) 39 CR (3d) 1.
[200]
Section 270AB of the South
Australia Criminal Law Consolidation Act 1935.
[201]
See Enker “Mens Rea and
Criminal Attempt” (1977) Am B Found Res J 845, at 848.
[202]
This argument is implicitly invoked
in McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at
445; Charleton, McDermott and Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at
259; Smith “Two Problems in Criminal Attempts” (1957) 70 Harv L Rev 427 at 434.
[203]
Enker “Mens Rea and Criminal
Attempt” (1977) Am B Found Res J 845 at 847, Holmes The Common Law
(Boston Little Brown 1881); Binchy “Criminal Liability, Attempting Non-Criminal
Acts – Part III” (1972) 106 ILTSJ 17, at 18.
[204]
[1999] 1 AC 82, At 145.
[205] Ashworth Principles
of Criminal Liability (5th ed Oxford University Press 2006) at
177.
[206]
See Hart “Intention and Punishment”
in Hart Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford University Press 1968) at
126-127.
[207]
See Law Reform Commission Report
on Homicide: Murder and Involuntary Manslaughter (LRC 87-2008) at 51-62.
[208]
R v Khan [1990] 2 All ER 783.
[209]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Working Paper on Codification of the criminal law: general principles:
inchoate offences: conspiracy, attempt and incitement (WP No 50 1973) at
61.
[210]
See Duff Criminal Attempts (Oxford
University Press 1996) at 13. See also Buxton “The Working Paper on Inchoate
Offences; Incitement and Attempt” [1973] Crim LR 656, 661; and Buxton
“Circumstances, Consequences, and Attempted Rape” [1984] Crim LR 25, 29.
[211]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Report on Attempt, and Impossibility in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and
Incitement (No 102 1980) at paragraphs 2.11 -2.12.
[212]
Williams Textbook of Criminal Law
(Stevens & Sons 1978) at 32. Williams and the literature he
criticises use the crime of abduction rather than rape as an illustrative
example, but the observations about abduction would apply to rape also.
[213]
Buxton “Circumstances, Consequences,
and Attempted Rape” [1984] Crim LR 25.
[214]
[1982] 1 WLR 762.
[215]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Report on Codification of the Criminal Law (No 143 1985) at paragraph
14.30.
[216]
Clause 49(2) of Draft Code in Law
Commission for England and Wales A Criminal Code for England and Wales,
Volume 1: Report and Draft Criminal Code Bill (No. 177 1989).
[217]
Law Commission for England and Wales
A Criminal Code for England and Wales, Volume 1: Report and Draft Criminal
Code Bill (No. 177 1989).
[218]
Ormerod, Smith & Hogan
Criminal Law (11th ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 416.
Law Commission for England and Wales Working Paper on Codification of
the criminal law: general principles: inchoate offences: conspiracy, attempt
and incitement (WP No 50 1973) at 73-74 and Report on Attempt, and
Impossibility in Relation to Attempt, Conspiracy and Incitement (No 102
1980) at 54-55.
[219]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Working Paper on Codification of the criminal law: general principles:
inchoate offences: conspiracy, attempt and incitement (WP No 50 1973) at
73.
[220]
R v Banks (1873) 12 Cox CC
393; Ransford (1874) 13 Cox CC; R v Chelmsford Justices ex p Amos
[1973] Crim LR 437; R v Goldman [2001] Crim LR 822.
[221]
R v Goldman [2001] Crim LR
822; Morton v Henderson (1956) JC 55.
[222]
R v De Kromme (1892) 17 Cox
CC 492.
[223]
Section 1(4)(a).
[224]
R v Déry [2006] SCC 53
affirming R v Dungey (1980) 51 CCC (2d) 86.
[225]
[2003] CLY 871. See Ormerod
Smith & Hogan: Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 411.
[226]
Section 25 of the Immigration Act
1971.
[227]
See Robbins “Double Inchoate Crimes”
(1989) 26 Harv J on Legis 1.
[228] Other prominent
examples are section 4 of the Offences Against the Person Act 1861
(soliciting murder) and section 71 of the Criminal Justice Act 2006
(conspiracy to commit a serious offence).
[229]
Section 9 of the Firearms and
Offensive Weapons Act 1990.
[230]
Article 15 of the Constitution of
Ireland. However, Hamilton P in Attorney General (SPUC) v Open Door
Counselling [1988] IR 593, 610 suggested the courts have a legitimate
constitutional function in extending the criminal law in order to protect
fundamental rights. As noted in Hogan and Whyte Kelly, The Irish
Constitution (4th ed LexisNexis 2003) at 1051-1052, subsequent
cases demonstrate a judicial view much in contrast with Hamilton P’s in that
they categorically rule out judicial extension of the criminal law. See Corway
v Independent Newspapers [1999] 4 IR 484 and de Gortari v
Smithwick (No 2) [2001] 1 ILRM 354.
[231]
See Chapter 1 of Report of the
Expert Group on the Codification of the Criminal Law Codifying the Criminal
Law (Government Publications 2004).
[232]
See Charleton, McDermott and Bolger Criminal
Law (Butterworths 1999) at 283-284.
[233]
Section 321O.
[234]
Section 71 of the Criminal
Justice Act 2006.
[235]
Section 1(4) of the Criminal
Attempts Act 1981. Excluded target offences include conspiracy as a
relational inchoate offence.
[236]
See Report of the Expert Group on
the Codification of the Criminal Law Codifying the Criminal Law
(Government Publications 2004) at 49.
[237]
Haughton v Smith [1975] AC 476.
[238]
R v Whyte [1910] 2 KB 124.
[239]
Haughton v Smith [1975] AC 476.
[240]
The argument here is influenced by
HLA Hart, “The House of Lords on Attempting the Impossible” in Hart Essays
in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Clarendon, Oxford, 1983) at 367-391.
[242]
[1983] 1 WLR 627.
[243]
(1889) 24 QBD 357.
[244]
(1892) 17 Cox CC 491.
[245]
(1864) 9 Cox CC 497.
[246]
See McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 436-437.
[248]
[1910] 2 KB 124.
[249]
Baron Bramwell’s example from R v
Collins (1864) 9 Cox CC 497, 498.
[250]
[1963] IR 169, 196-197.
[251]
218 Wis.2d 526, 581 N.W.2d 544
(Wis.App.1998).
[252]
In Dlugash 363 NE 2d 1155
(1977, New York) shooting a corpse intending to kill was upheld as attempted
murder.
[253]
Ashworth Principles of Criminal
Law (5th ed Oxford University Press 2006) at 449-451.
[256]
[1985] AC 560, 562.
[257]
[1985] AC 560, 580.
[258]
See [1987] AC 1, 22.
[260]
[1975] AC 476, 501.
[261]
Ormerod Smith & Hogan:
Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 425.
[262]
Example adapted from Jeremy Horder’s
book review of Duff Criminal Attempts (Oxford University Press 1996),
which appears in (1997) 113 LQR 688.
[263]
English translation adapted from
Rocco The Italian Penal Code (Sweet & Maxwell, 1978) at 16 and McAuley
and McCutcheon Criminal Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 441.
[264]
Donnelly “Possibility, Impossibility
and Extraordinariness in Attempts” (forthcoming).
[265]
Donnelly “Possibility, Impossibility
and Extraordinariness in Attempts” (forthcoming).
[266]
Smith “Attempts, impossibility and
the test of rational motivation” in Gower (ed) Auckland Law School Centenary
Lectures (Auckland Legal Research Foundation 1983) at 25.
[267]
Smith “Attempts, impossibility and
the test of rational motivation” in Gower (ed) Auckland Law School Centenary
Lectures (Auckland Legal Research Foundation 1983) at 37 and 42.
[268]
Based on Walsh J’s obiter dictum in the Supreme Court decision in
The People (Attorney General) v Sullivan [1964] IR 169.
[269]
(1859) 1 F & F 511; 175 ER 831.
[270]
[1959] Crim LR 209.
[271]
See Wasik “Abandoning Criminal
Intent” [1980] Crim LR 785, 786-787.
[272]
DPP v Stonehouse [1978] AC
55; [1977] 3 WLR 143, 150, per Lord Diplock.
[273]
(1985) 23 CCC (3d) 385.
[274]
R v Kosh (1965) 44 CR 185; R
v Goodman (1832) 22 UCCP 338. There are no recent cases; the Supreme
Court of Canada has not had occasion to address the issue.
[275]
R v Page [1933] ALR 374.
[276]
R v Lankford [1959] Crim LR
209.
[277]
[1964] IR 169, 196-197.
[278]
Sections 5.01(4), 5.02(3), and
5.03(6) of the Model Penal Code.
[279]
See Wechsler, Jones and Korn “The
Treatment of Inchoate Crimes in the Model Penal Code of the American Law
Institute: Attempt, Solicitation, and Conspiracy” (1961) 61 Columbia Law Review
571at 615-616, citing, among other cases, Weaver v State 116 Ga 550, 42
SE 745 (1902); Parker v State 29 Ga App 26, 113 SE 218 (1922).
[280]
Section 24 of the German Penal Code.
[281]
France, Norway, Malta, Switzerland.
[282]
Article 56 of the Italian Penal
Code. See McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal Liability (Round Hall
Press 2000) at 451.
[283]
Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 395-396, and at 388-389.
[284]
Stuart Canadian Criminal Law
(4th ed Carswell 2001) at 671.
[285]
See Fletcher Basic Concepts of
Criminal Law (Oxford University Press 1998) at 183.
[286]
See Wechsler, Jones and Korn “The
Treatment of Inchoate Crimes in the Model Penal Code of the American Law
Institute: Attempt, Solicitation, and Conspiracy” (1961) 61 Columbia Law Review
571 at 617-618.
[287]
This expresses the reasoning that
common law courts have provided in declining to acknowledge a defence of
abandonment. See Kosh (1965) 44 CR 185.
[288]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Report on Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime (No 300
2006) at paragraph 6.57.
[289]
Quoted in Wechsler, Jones and Korn
“The Treatment of Inchoate Crimes in the Model Penal Code of the American Law
Institute: Attempt, Solicitation, and Conspiracy” (1961) 61 Columbia Law Review
571 at 616.
[290]
Duff Criminal Attempts
(Oxford University Press 1996) at 396.
[291]
See Stuart Canadian Criminal Law
(4th ed Carswell 2001) at 671, Fletcher Basic Concepts of
Criminal Law (Oxford University Press 1998) at 183.
[292]
See McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 451 citing the German case, Judgment
of 7 BGHSt, 1995, 296. Case discussed by Fletcher Basic Concepts of
Criminal Law (Oxford University Press 1998) at 183.
[293]
R v Journeyman
Tailors (1721) 8 Mod 10.
[294]
R v Jones (1832)
110 ER 485, 487. It has been suggested by commentators that Lord Denman
subsequently rejected his own definition of conspiracy. See, for example,
Charleton, McDermott and Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 2000) at 296,
Ormerod Smith & Hogan: Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press
2005) at 359. But in the case cited as revealing the supposed rejection –
R v Peck (1839) 9 A and E 686, 690 – Lord Denman interjects “I do not
think the antithesis very correct” when counsel quotes the definition.
This literally signals approval, not rejection of the previous dictum.
Furthermore, there is nothing in the Peck decision that indicates a
retreat from the expansive Jones definition.
[295]
R v Parnell (1881)
14 Cox 508, Connolly v Loughney (1953) 87 ILTR 49, Hegarty v Governor
of Limerick Prison [1998] 1 IR 412.
[296]
Parnell’ Case (1881)
14 Cox 508, Kamara v DPP [1973] 2 All ER 1242.
[297]
Ormerod Smith &
Hogan: Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 374.
[298]
Section 70 of the Criminal
Justice Act 2006.
[299]
See Lally “Seven Charged
over Attempted Robbery” The Irish Times 6 November 2007.
[300]
Leigh (1775) 1 C
& K 28n; 174 ER 697n; 2 Camp 372; 170 ER 1188n; Tibbits [1902] 1 KB
77. See Charleton, McDermott and Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths
1999) at 298.
[301]
Willes J in Mulcahy v
R (1868) LR 3 HL 306, 317.
[302]
Orchard “Agreement in Criminal
Conspiracy” [1974] Crim LR 297, at 300.
[303]
Simmonds (1967) 51 Cr
App R 317, 322; R v Murphy (1837) 173 ER 502, approved by Keane CJ in Attorney
General v Oldridge [2001] 2 ILRM 125, 133.
[304]
As the House of Lords
recognised in R v Doot [1973] 1 All ER 940.
[305]
People (AG) v Keane
(1975) 1 Frewen 392.
[306]
Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 300.
[307]
R v Plummer [1902] 2 KB
339.
[308]
DPP v Shannon [1975] AC
717, R v Coughlan (1976) 64 Cr App R 11.
[309]
(1982) 148 CLR 668.
[310]
People (AG) v Keane
(1975) 1 Frewen 392, 399.
[311]
Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 300.
[312] Mulcahy
v R (1868) LR 3 HL 306, 317.
[313]
(1943) 1 Frewen 42.
[314]
(1975) 1 Frewen 392.
[315]
Causing explosions being an
offence under section 3 of Explosive Substances Act 1883.
[316]
(1975) 1 Frewen 392, 395.
[317]
(1943) 1 Frewen 42.
[318]
(1975) 1 Frewen 392.
[319]
Dennis “The Rationale of
Criminal Conspiracy” (1977) 93 LQR 39 at 40.
[320]
(1975) 1 Frewen 392.
[321]
(1975) 1 Frewen 392, 397.
[322]
R v Murphy (1837) 173
ER 502; R v Rankin (1848) 7 St Tr (NS) 712, 787. But there are older
cases such as Attorny v Starling (1664) 83 ER 1164, 1167, 1179, 1184;
implying the contrary: that is, that conspirators must have met in person at
some stage.
[324]
R v Murphy (1837) 173
ER 502. Approved by Keane CJ in Attorney General v Oldridge [2001] 2 ILRM 125, 133.
[325]
R v Doot [1973] AC 807,
823.
[326]
United States v Bruno
(1939) 105 F 2d 921.
[327]
See Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 301-302.
[328]
[1998] 1 IR 412, 425.
[329]
[1958] Crim LR 422, 437.
[330]
See Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 279-285.
[331]
[1973] AC 807.
[332]
[1991] ILRM 365, 372.
[333]
Samson [1991] 2 QB 130;
Liangsiriprasert v Government of the United States of America [1991] 1
AC 225.
[334]
[1957] AC 602.
[335]
Section 465(4).
[336]
Section 465(3).
[337]
R v Robinson (1746) 1
Leach 37; R v Whitehouse (1852) 6 Cox CC 38; Kowbel v R [1954]
SCR 498; Mawji v R [1957] AC 126.
[338]
Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 319.
[339]
[1981] IR 412.
[340]
[1981] IR 412, 448-449.
[341]
Article 40.1.
[342]
Henchy J also suggested the
rule had been “swept away by legislation and by judicial decisions”: [1981] IR
412, 449.
[343]
(1960) 364 US 51.
[344]
Section 2(2)(a).
[345]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at
paragraphs 9.28-9.29.
[346]
The same could be said about
the common law rule of evidence that one spouse was not a competent witness
against the other, yet the Court of Criminal Appeal in The People (DPP) v T
(1988) 3 Frewen 141 indicated that this rule would be unconstitutional.
See Hogan and Whyte Kelly: The Irish Constitution (4th ed
LexisNexis 2003) at 1842. See also Law Reform Commission Report on
Competence and Compellability of Spouses as Witnesses (LRC 13 – 1985).
[348]
Attorney General for
England and Wales v Brandon Book Publishers Ltd [1986] IR 597.
[349]
[1985] IR 532 (High Court),
[1991] ILRM 465 (Supreme Court).
[350]
(1890) 24 QBD 420.
[351]
See Dennis “The Rationale of
Criminal Conspiracy” (1977) 93 LQR 39 at 54-55.
[352]
R v Tyrrell [1894] 1 QB
710, R v Whitehouse [1977] QB 868.
[353]
(1906) 75 LJKB 470, described
by Dennis “The Rationale of Criminal Conspiracy” (1977) 93 LQR 39 at 55.
[354]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at
144-152.
[355]
(1906) 75 LJKB 470, described
by Dennis “The Rationale of Criminal Conspiracy” (1977) 93 LQR 39 at 55.
[356]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at
paragraph 10.31.
[357]
Section 2(2)(b) of the Criminal
Law Act 1977.
[358]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Consultation Paper on Conspiracy and Attempts (CP No 183 2007) at
150-151.
[359]
See Ormerod Smith &
Hogan: Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 374-382.
Ormerod is concerned to describe the current law in England and Wales,
which is covered by statute. His classification, however, applies aptly
to the common law.
[360]
O’Brien [1954] SCR 666,
668.
[361]
Per Asquith J in Clayton
(1943) 33 Cr App R 113, 119.
[362]
R v Porter [1980] NI
18.
[363]
Mulcahy (1868) LR 3 HL
306, at 317; Yip Chiu-cheung [1994] 2 All ER 924.
[364]
[1967] 2 AC 224.
[365]
[1986] AC 27.
[366]
(1990) 6 BNIL.
[367]
See Ormerod Smith &
Hogan: Criminal Law (11th Ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 376.
[369]
[1986] AC 27.
[370]
Ormerod “Mens Rea in
Conspiracy” (2006) Current Legal Problems 185.
[372]
R v Blamires Transport
Services Ltd [1964] 1 QB 278.
[373]
R v Booth [1999]
Crim LR 144.
[374]
(1985) 82 Cr App R 226.
[375]
Nernich (1915) 24 CCC
256.
[376]
See Robbins “Double Inchoate
Crimes” (1989) 26 Harv J on Legis 1.
[377]
At paragraphs 2.113-2.121.
[378]
(1881) 14 Cox 508.
[379]
[1973] 2 All ER 1242.
[381]
(1953) 87 ILTR 49.
[382]
Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 308.
[383]
R v Cooke [1986] AC
909.
[384]
O'Sullivan v Conroy,
Barr J, High Court, 31 July 1997; Myles v Sreenan [1999] 4 IR 294; AG v Oldridge [2000]
1 IR 593; [2001] 2 ILRM 125; People (DPP) v O’Brien
CCA 17 June 2002.
[385]
Myles v Sreenan [1999] 4 IR 294.
[386]
Attorney General v Oldridge
[2000] 1 IR 593; [2001] 2 ILRM 125.
[387]
Scott v Metropolitan Police
Commissioner [1975] AC 819; [1974] 3 All ER 1032, 1039,
per Viscount Dilhorne.
[389]
[1988] IR 593; [1987] ILRM
477.
[390]
[1988] IR 593; [1987] ILRM
477.
[391]
[1973] AC 435; [1972] 2 All ER
898.
[392]
[1988] IR 593; [1987] ILRM 477.
[393]
Those conditions set out in section
1(1) of the UK’s Abortion Act 1967.
[394]
Shaw v DPP [1962] AC 220.
[395]
Knuller v DPP [1973] AC 435.
[396]
Attorney General (SPUC) v Open
Door Counselling [1988] IR 593.
[397]
Knuller v DPP [1973] AC 435.
[398]
And presumably also attempt and
incitement to outrage public decency, though these examples of inchoate
offences were not mentioned in Knuller.
[399]
[1981] ILRM 91.
[400]
DPP v Withers [1975] AC 842.
[401]
See McAleese “Note on Criminal Law –
Public Mischief” [1982] 4 DULJ 110.
[402]
R v Boston (1923) 33 CLR 386;
R v Howes (1971) 2 SASR 293. See Charleton, McDermott and
Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 307.
[403]
Sayre “Criminal Conspiracy” (1922)
35 Harv L Rev 393, at 413.
[404]
[1973] AC 435, 463.
[405]
For explication see Duff Criminal
Attempts (Oxford University Press 1996) at 394 and McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 429.
[406]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 427-430. Endorsed by Keane CJ in
Attorney General v Oldridge [2001] 2 ILRM 125, 132.
[407]
United States and England and Wales.
[408]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 428-429.
[409]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 429.
[410]
McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 429.
[411]
Myles v Sreenan [1999] 4 IR 294.
[412]
Attorney General v Oldridge [2001] 2 ILRM 125, 132.
[413]
Law Commission for England and Wales
Working Paper on Codification of the criminal law: general principles:
inchoate offences: conspiracy, attempt and incitement (WP No 50 1973), Report
on Conspiracy and Criminal Law Reform (No 76 1976), and Report on
Criminal Law: Conspiracy to Defraud (No 228 1994).
[414]
Report on Fraud (No 276
2002).
[415]
R v Gralewicz [1980] 2 SCR
493.
[416]
See Stuart Canadian Criminal Law
(4th ed Carswell 2001) at 678.
[417]
Scott v Metropolitan Police
Commissioner [1974] 3 All ER 1032, 1039.
[418]
[1978] AC 979.
[419]
[1978] AC 979, 996.
[420]
[1964] IR 169.
[421]
At paragraph 3.78.
[422]
See discussion above at paragraphs
2.129-2.152.
[423]
See above at paragraph 3.79.
[424]
[1964] IR 169.
[425] See above at
paragraphs 2.153-2.163.
[426]
R v Higgins
(1801) 2 East 5 is the seminal case recognising incitement as an offence.
See Scott “The Common Law Offence of Incitement to Commit Crime” (1975) 4
Anglo-Am L Rev 289.
[427]
Prohibition of
Incitement to Hatred Act 1989.
[428]
People (DPP) v
Murtagh [1990] 1 IR 339, 342.
[429]
Holmes JA in S v
Mkosiyana (1966) 4 SA 655, 658, quoted in R v Goldman [2001] Crim LR
822; [2001] EWCA Crim 1684, McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal Liability (Round
Hall Press 2000) at 431, Ormerod, Smith & Hogan Criminal Law (11th
ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 351.
[430]
Section 4 of the Offences
Against the Person Act 1861.
[431]
[1997] Crim LR 897.
[432]
Race Relations Board
v Applin [1973] QB 815, R v Evans [1986] Crim LR 470.
[433]
R(Lanktree) v
M’Carthy (1902-1903) 3 New Irish Jurist & Loc. Gov’t Rev. 76, 81.
[434]
S v Mkosiyana
(1966) 4 SA 655, 658. Emphasis added.
[435]
R v Sirat (1985) 83 Cr
App R 41, R v Ransford (1874) 13 Cox CC 9, R v Banks (1873) 12
Cox CC 393.
[436]
People (DPP) v Murtagh
[1990] 1 IR 339, 342.
[437]
See DPP v Armstrong
[2000] Crim LR 379, R v Goldman [2001] Crim LR 822.
[438]
(1949) 1 Frewen 95.
[439]
(1949) 1 Frewen 95.
[440]
R v Higgins (1801) 2
East 5, 22. Quoted in The People (Attorney General) v Capaldi
(1949) 1 Frewen 95, 96-97.
[441]
R (O) v Coventry
Magistrates’ Court [2004] Crim LR 948.
[442]
(1881) 7 QBD 244.
[443]
Contrary to section 4, Offences
Against the Person Act 1861. Soliciting murder, that is, incitement
to murder is contained in this 1861 Act in Ireland and England. The
provision merely states the common law offence. Unlike incitement to hatred in
Ireland’s Prohibition of Incitement to Hatred Act 1989 Act (and indeed
the offence of encouragement of terrorism in section 1 of the UK’s Terrorism
Act 2006), the 1861 Act did not enact a new incitement offence because it
would exist anyway at common law by virtue of the general relational inchoate
offence of incitement attaching to the special part offence of murder.
[444]
R v El-Faisal [2004] EWCA Crim 456, R v Abu Hamza [2006] EWCA Crim 2918.
[445]
Invicta Plastics Ltd v
Clare [1976] RTR 251; [1976] Crim LR 131.
[446]
[1997] EWCA Crim 1833; [1997]
Crim LR 897.
[447]
Section 7(1).
[448]
See below at paragraphs
4.40-4.47.
[449]
S v Mkosiyana (1966) 4
SA 655, 658.
[450]
Section 2A(1) of the Crimes
Act 1958 (Victoria).
[451] Weisman and
Graae “Statutory Proposal on Inchoate Crime” (1979) 22 Howard LJ 217.
[452]
Final Report of the
Kentucky Penal Code Revision Project of the Criminal Justice Council
(2003). Final Report of the Illinois Criminal Code Rewrite and Reform
Commission (2003). The Reporter on these reports was Paul H Robinson.
[453]
Section 4 of the Offences
Against the Person Act 1861.
[454]
Section 464 of the Criminal
Code of Canada.
[455]
Clause 47 of Draft Criminal
Code in A Criminal Code for England and Wales, Volume 1: Report and Draft
Criminal Code Bill (No 177 1989).
[456]
R v Goldman [2001] Crim
LR 822; DPP v Armstrong [2000] Crim LR 379; R (O) v Coventry
Magistrates’ Court [2004] Crim LR 948.
[457]
(1801) 2 East 5, 102 ER 269.
[458]
(1881) 7 QBD 244, 248 and 251.
[459]
Though a strong case can be
made the other way in light of cases such as Invicta Plastics [1976]
Crim LR 131, which is discussed below at paragraph 4.27.
[460]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime
(No 300 2006) at 34.
[461]
The statement was from Ormerod
Smith & Hogan: Criminal Law (11th ed Oxford University
Press 2005) at 353-354.
[462]
See McAuley and McCutcheon Criminal
Liability (Round Hall Press 2000) at 430.
[463]
See Stannard “Making up for
the Missing Element: A Sideways Look at Attempts” (1987) 7 Legal Studies 194.
[464]
Invicta Plastics Ltd v
Clare [1976] Crim LR 131, [1976] RTR 251.
[465]
Section 1(2)(b)(ii) of the Terrorism
Act 2006.
[466]
Contrary to section 5 of the Child
Trafficking and Pornography Act 1998.
[467]
Section 2 of the Child
Trafficking and Pornography Act 1998 provides the definition of child
pornography.
[468]
R v Curr [1968]
2 QB 944.
[469]
See Williams Textbook of
Criminal Law (2nd ed Stevens & Sons 1983). See discussion of the
consequences/circumstances distinction in Chapter 2 above at paragraphs
2.100-2.107.
[470]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime
(No 300 2006) at 34. Ormerod Smith & Hogan: Criminal Law (11th
ed Oxford University Press 2005) at 354.
[471]
[1976] Crim LR 131; [1976] RTR
251.
[472]
[1994] Crim LR 365.
[473] See
Smith’s commentary on the case: [1994] Crim LR 366. Charleton, McDermott
and Bolger Criminal Law (Butterworths 1999) at 335. Heaton Criminal
Law Textbook (Oxford University Press 2006) at 514.
[474]
See above at paragraphs
2.93-2.95.
[476]
[1968] 2 QB 944.
[477]
Heaton Criminal Law
Textbook (Oxford University Press 2006) at 514.
[478]
See Heaton Criminal Law
Textbook (Oxford University Press 2006) at 513.
[479]
[1968] 2 QB 944.
[480]
Christie Inchoate Crimes:
Incitement, Conspiracy and Attempts in Scottish Criminal Law (Edinburgh
Sweet & Maxwell 2001).
[481]
For example, the 1989 Act uses
“stir up” rather than “incite” to describe the offence. See Daly “Reform
of the Prohibition of Incitement to Hatred Act 1989 – Part I” (2007) 17 ICLJ
16.
[482]
R v De Kromme (1892) 17
Cox CC 492.
[483]
Section 5(7) of the Criminal
Law Act 1977 (Eng).
[484]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime
(No 300 2006) at 32.
[485]
R v Sirat (1985)
83 Cr App R 41, R v Evans [1986] Crim LR 470.
[486]
See above at paragraphs
2.113-2.121.
[487]
Section 7 of the Criminal
Law Act 1997 read in conjunction with section 2 of the same Act.
[488]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime
(No 300 2006) at 21-23.
[489]
Which in England and Wales is
statutory conspiracy: section 1(1) of the Criminal Law Act 1977.
[490]
Spencer “Trying to Help
Another Person to Commit a Crime” in P Smith (ed) Essays in Honour of JC
Smith (Butterworths 1987), Law Commission for England and Wales Report
on Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime (No 300 2006).
[491]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime
(No 300 2006).
[492]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime
(No 300 2006) at 48.
[493]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime
(No 300 2006) at 151. section 18 of draft Bill.
[494]
Sullivan “Inchoate Liability
for Assisting and Encouraging Crime – The Law Commission Report” [2006] Crim LR
1047, 1049.
[495]
Law Commission for England and
Wales Report on Participating in Crime (No 305 2007).
[496] Law
Commission for England and Wales Report on Inchoate Liability for Assisting
and Encouraging Crime (No 300 2006).
[497]
See Sullivan “Inchoate
Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime – The Law Commission Report”
[2006] Crim LR 1047, at 1054 for a variant.
[498]
See Roberts “Taking the Burden
of Proof Seriously” [1995] Crim LR 783.
[499]
Article 40.6.1°(i).
[500]
Article 10.
[501]
[1997] Crim LR 897.
[502]
Marlow v United Kingdom
[2001] EHRLR 444.
[503]
(1969) 395 US 444.
[504]
Alexander “Incitement and
Freedom of Speech” in Kretzmer and Hazan (eds) Freedom of Speech and
Incitement Against Democracy (Kluwer 2000) at 113-114.
[505]
See above at paragraphs at
4.02 and 4.06.
[506]
[2001] Crim LR 822.
[508]
Section 54 of the Criminal
Law Act 1977.
[509]
[2005] EWCA Crim 2827; [2006]
1 Cr App R 20.
[510]
[1983] 1 All ER 189. Fitzmaurice
applied DPP v Nock and Alsford [1978] AC 979, discussed above at
paragraph 3.78.
[511]
(1962) 47 Cr App R 37.
[512]
See discussion of impossible
attempts above at paragraphs 2.129-2.152.
[513]
See above at paragraphs
2.153-2.163.
[514]
Section 5.02 of the Model
Penal Code.
[515]
Of course it is not necessary
for incitement that the incitement was actually an operative factor in making
an inictee proceed towards crime.